Slide 1

Slide 1 text

Strongly unbounded colorings (joint work with Assaf Rinot) Chris Lambie-Hanson Department of Mathematics and Applied Mathematics Virginia Commonwealth University Kobe Set Theory Workshop on the occasion of Saka´ e Fuchino’s retirement 11 March 2021

Slide 2

Slide 2 text

Prologue Productivity of chain conditions

Slide 3

Slide 3 text

Knaster property

Slide 4

Slide 4 text

Knaster property Drawing by Leon Jesmanowicz

Slide 5

Slide 5 text

Knaster property Drawing by Leon Jesmanowicz Throughout the talk, κ denotes a regular uncountable cardinal.

Slide 6

Slide 6 text

Knaster property Drawing by Leon Jesmanowicz Throughout the talk, κ denotes a regular uncountable cardinal. Recall that a poset P is κ-Knaster if, whenever, A ∈ [P]κ, there is B ∈ [A]κ consisting of pairwise compatible conditions.

Slide 7

Slide 7 text

Knaster property Drawing by Leon Jesmanowicz Throughout the talk, κ denotes a regular uncountable cardinal. Recall that a poset P is κ-Knaster if, whenever, A ∈ [P]κ, there is B ∈ [A]κ consisting of pairwise compatible conditions. The κ-Knaster property is a strengthening of the κ-cc.

Slide 8

Slide 8 text

Knaster property Drawing by Leon Jesmanowicz Throughout the talk, κ denotes a regular uncountable cardinal. Recall that a poset P is κ-Knaster if, whenever, A ∈ [P]κ, there is B ∈ [A]κ consisting of pairwise compatible conditions. The κ-Knaster property is a strengthening of the κ-cc. In contrast to the κ-cc, the κ-Knaster property is always productive: if P and Q are κ-Knaster, then P × Q are κ-Knaster.

Slide 9

Slide 9 text

Infinite productivity For an infinite cardinal θ, we say that the κ-Knaster property is θ-productive if, whenever {Pi | i < θ} are all κ-Knaster, the full-support product i<θ Pi is κ-Knaster.

Slide 10

Slide 10 text

Infinite productivity For an infinite cardinal θ, we say that the κ-Knaster property is θ-productive if, whenever {Pi | i < θ} are all κ-Knaster, the full-support product i<θ Pi is κ-Knaster. It’s not hard to show that, if κ is weakly compact, then the κ-Knaster property is <κ-productive.

Slide 11

Slide 11 text

Infinite productivity For an infinite cardinal θ, we say that the κ-Knaster property is θ-productive if, whenever {Pi | i < θ} are all κ-Knaster, the full-support product i<θ Pi is κ-Knaster. It’s not hard to show that, if κ is weakly compact, then the κ-Knaster property is <κ-productive. Theorem (Cox-L¨ ucke, ’17) Assuming the consistency of a weakly compact cardinal, there is consistently an inaccessible cardinal κ that is not weakly compact for which the κ-Knaster property is <κ-productive.

Slide 12

Slide 12 text

Infinite productivity For an infinite cardinal θ, we say that the κ-Knaster property is θ-productive if, whenever {Pi | i < θ} are all κ-Knaster, the full-support product i<θ Pi is κ-Knaster. It’s not hard to show that, if κ is weakly compact, then the κ-Knaster property is <κ-productive. Theorem (Cox-L¨ ucke, ’17) Assuming the consistency of a weakly compact cardinal, there is consistently an inaccessible cardinal κ that is not weakly compact for which the κ-Knaster property is <κ-productive. Theorem (LH-L¨ ucke, ’18) If the κ-Knaster property is ℵ0-productive, then κ is weakly compact in L.

Slide 13

Slide 13 text

Accessible cardinals The results of the previous slide left open the question of whether the κ-Knaster property can consistently be infinitely productive for some accessible cardinal κ, e.g., κ = ℵ2 or κ = ℵω+1.

Slide 14

Slide 14 text

Accessible cardinals The results of the previous slide left open the question of whether the κ-Knaster property can consistently be infinitely productive for some accessible cardinal κ, e.g., κ = ℵ2 or κ = ℵω+1. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [1]) Suppose that κ is a successor cardinal. Then there is a κ-Knaster poset P such that Pℵ0 is not κ-cc.

Slide 15

Slide 15 text

Accessible cardinals The results of the previous slide left open the question of whether the κ-Knaster property can consistently be infinitely productive for some accessible cardinal κ, e.g., κ = ℵ2 or κ = ℵω+1. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [1]) Suppose that κ is a successor cardinal. Then there is a κ-Knaster poset P such that Pℵ0 is not κ-cc. The proof of this theorem involved colorings c : [κ]2 → ω with strong unboundedness properties and initiated a systematic investigation of such colorings, their variations, and their applications.

Slide 16

Slide 16 text

References [1] Chris Lambie-Hanson and Assaf Rinot, Knaster and friends I: Closed colorings and precalibers, Algebra Universalis 79 (2018), no. 4, Art. 90, 39. MR 3878671 [2] , Knaster and friends II: The C-sequence number, J. Math. Log. 21 (2021), no. 01, 2150002. [3] , Knaster and friends III: Subadditive colorings, (2021), In preparation.

Slide 17

Slide 17 text

Chapter 1 Strongly unbounded colorings

Slide 18

Slide 18 text

U(κ, µ, θ, χ)

Slide 19

Slide 19 text

U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Definition U(κ, µ, θ, χ) asserts the existence of a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ such that,

Slide 20

Slide 20 text

U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Definition U(κ, µ, θ, χ) asserts the existence of a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ such that, for every χ < χ and A ⊆ [κ]χ consisting of κ-many pairwise disjoint sets,

Slide 21

Slide 21 text

U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Definition U(κ, µ, θ, χ) asserts the existence of a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ such that, for every χ < χ and A ⊆ [κ]χ consisting of κ-many pairwise disjoint sets, and for every color i < θ,

Slide 22

Slide 22 text

U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Definition U(κ, µ, θ, χ) asserts the existence of a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ such that, for every χ < χ and A ⊆ [κ]χ consisting of κ-many pairwise disjoint sets, and for every color i < θ, there is B ⊆ A of size µ such that, for all a < b, both from B, we have min(c[a × b]) > i.

Slide 23

Slide 23 text

U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Definition U(κ, µ, θ, χ) asserts the existence of a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ such that, for every χ < χ and A ⊆ [κ]χ consisting of κ-many pairwise disjoint sets, and for every color i < θ, there is B ⊆ A of size µ such that, for all a < b, both from B, we have min(c[a × b]) > i. U(κ, µ, θ, χ) can be seen as asserting a strong failure of Ramsey’s theorem at κ.

Slide 24

Slide 24 text

U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Definition U(κ, µ, θ, χ) asserts the existence of a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ such that, for every χ < χ and A ⊆ [κ]χ consisting of κ-many pairwise disjoint sets, and for every color i < θ, there is B ⊆ A of size µ such that, for all a < b, both from B, we have min(c[a × b]) > i. U(κ, µ, θ, χ) can be seen as asserting a strong failure of Ramsey’s theorem at κ. Note that, for all µ ≤ µ and χ ≤ χ, U(κ, µ, θ, χ) implies U(κ, µ , θ, χ ), but there is no such obvious monotonicity in the third coordinate.

Slide 25

Slide 25 text

Failure of infinite productivity Lemma Suppose that θ ≤ χ < κ are infinite, regular cardinals, κ is (<χ)-inaccessible, and U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds. Then there is a poset P such that

Slide 26

Slide 26 text

Failure of infinite productivity Lemma Suppose that θ ≤ χ < κ are infinite, regular cardinals, κ is (<χ)-inaccessible, and U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds. Then there is a poset P such that • P is χ-directed closed;

Slide 27

Slide 27 text

Failure of infinite productivity Lemma Suppose that θ ≤ χ < κ are infinite, regular cardinals, κ is (<χ)-inaccessible, and U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds. Then there is a poset P such that • P is χ-directed closed; • Pτ is κ-Knaster for all τ < θ;

Slide 28

Slide 28 text

Failure of infinite productivity Lemma Suppose that θ ≤ χ < κ are infinite, regular cardinals, κ is (<χ)-inaccessible, and U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds. Then there is a poset P such that • P is χ-directed closed; • Pτ is κ-Knaster for all τ < θ; • Pθ is not κ-c.c.

Slide 29

Slide 29 text

Failure of infinite productivity Lemma Suppose that θ ≤ χ < κ are infinite, regular cardinals, κ is (<χ)-inaccessible, and U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds. Then there is a poset P such that • P is χ-directed closed; • Pτ is κ-Knaster for all τ < θ; • Pθ is not κ-c.c. Sketch of proof. Let c : [κ]2 → θ witness U(κ, κ, θ, χ).

Slide 30

Slide 30 text

Failure of infinite productivity Lemma Suppose that θ ≤ χ < κ are infinite, regular cardinals, κ is (<χ)-inaccessible, and U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds. Then there is a poset P such that • P is χ-directed closed; • Pτ is κ-Knaster for all τ < θ; • Pθ is not κ-c.c. Sketch of proof. Let c : [κ]2 → θ witness U(κ, κ, θ, χ). For all i < θ, let Pi be the poset whose conditions are all sets x ∈ [κ]<χ such that min(c“[x]2) > i, ordered by reverse inclusion.

Slide 31

Slide 31 text

Failure of infinite productivity Lemma Suppose that θ ≤ χ < κ are infinite, regular cardinals, κ is (<χ)-inaccessible, and U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds. Then there is a poset P such that • P is χ-directed closed; • Pτ is κ-Knaster for all τ < θ; • Pθ is not κ-c.c. Sketch of proof. Let c : [κ]2 → θ witness U(κ, κ, θ, χ). For all i < θ, let Pi be the poset whose conditions are all sets x ∈ [κ]<χ such that min(c“[x]2) > i, ordered by reverse inclusion. Let P be the lottery sum i<θ Pi .

Slide 32

Slide 32 text

Failure of infinite productivity Lemma Suppose that θ ≤ χ < κ are infinite, regular cardinals, κ is (<χ)-inaccessible, and U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds. Then there is a poset P such that • P is χ-directed closed; • Pτ is κ-Knaster for all τ < θ; • Pθ is not κ-c.c. Sketch of proof. Let c : [κ]2 → θ witness U(κ, κ, θ, χ). For all i < θ, let Pi be the poset whose conditions are all sets x ∈ [κ]<χ such that min(c“[x]2) > i, ordered by reverse inclusion. Let P be the lottery sum i<θ Pi . Now check that P works.

Slide 33

Slide 33 text

Further proof sketch?

Slide 34

Slide 34 text

Productivity at successor cardinals

Slide 35

Slide 35 text

Productivity at successor cardinals The principle U(· · · ) has been implicit in a variety of previous work. Particularly notable for us is the following result of Todorcevic.

Slide 36

Slide 36 text

Productivity at successor cardinals The principle U(· · · ) has been implicit in a variety of previous work. Particularly notable for us is the following result of Todorcevic. Theorem (Todorcevic) For every infinite cardinal λ, U(λ+, λ+, ℵ0, cf(λ)) holds.

Slide 37

Slide 37 text

Productivity at successor cardinals The principle U(· · · ) has been implicit in a variety of previous work. Particularly notable for us is the following result of Todorcevic. Theorem (Todorcevic) For every infinite cardinal λ, U(λ+, λ+, ℵ0, cf(λ)) holds. Corollary For every successor cardinal κ, the κ-Knaster property fails to be ℵ0-productive.

Slide 38

Slide 38 text

Provable instances of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Given a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ, an ordinal β < κ, and a color i < θ, let Dc ≤i (β) := {α < β | c(α, β) ≤ i}.

Slide 39

Slide 39 text

Provable instances of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Given a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ, an ordinal β < κ, and a color i < θ, let Dc ≤i (β) := {α < β | c(α, β) ≤ i}. We say that c is closed if Dc ≤i (β) is a closed subset of β for all β < κ and i < θ.

Slide 40

Slide 40 text

Provable instances of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Given a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ, an ordinal β < κ, and a color i < θ, let Dc ≤i (β) := {α < β | c(α, β) ≤ i}. We say that c is closed if Dc ≤i (β) is a closed subset of β for all β < κ and i < θ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [1]) Suppose that θ, χ < κ are regular cardinals. Any one of the following entails U(κ, κ, θ, χ).

Slide 41

Slide 41 text

Provable instances of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Given a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ, an ordinal β < κ, and a color i < θ, let Dc ≤i (β) := {α < β | c(α, β) ≤ i}. We say that c is closed if Dc ≤i (β) is a closed subset of β for all β < κ and i < θ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [1]) Suppose that θ, χ < κ are regular cardinals. Any one of the following entails U(κ, κ, θ, χ). 1 There is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(≥ χ).

Slide 42

Slide 42 text

Provable instances of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Given a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ, an ordinal β < κ, and a color i < θ, let Dc ≤i (β) := {α < β | c(α, β) ≤ i}. We say that c is closed if Dc ≤i (β) is a closed subset of β for all β < κ and i < θ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [1]) Suppose that θ, χ < κ are regular cardinals. Any one of the following entails U(κ, κ, θ, χ). 1 There is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(≥ χ). 2 κ = λ+ and λ is regular.

Slide 43

Slide 43 text

Provable instances of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Given a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ, an ordinal β < κ, and a color i < θ, let Dc ≤i (β) := {α < β | c(α, β) ≤ i}. We say that c is closed if Dc ≤i (β) is a closed subset of β for all β < κ and i < θ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [1]) Suppose that θ, χ < κ are regular cardinals. Any one of the following entails U(κ, κ, θ, χ). 1 There is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(≥ χ). 2 κ = λ+ and λ is regular. 3 κ = λ+ and cf(λ) = θ.

Slide 44

Slide 44 text

Provable instances of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Given a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ, an ordinal β < κ, and a color i < θ, let Dc ≤i (β) := {α < β | c(α, β) ≤ i}. We say that c is closed if Dc ≤i (β) is a closed subset of β for all β < κ and i < θ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [1]) Suppose that θ, χ < κ are regular cardinals. Any one of the following entails U(κ, κ, θ, χ). 1 There is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(≥ χ). 2 κ = λ+ and λ is regular. 3 κ = λ+ and cf(λ) = θ. 4 (κ) holds.

Slide 45

Slide 45 text

Provable instances of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Given a coloring c : [κ]2 → θ, an ordinal β < κ, and a color i < θ, let Dc ≤i (β) := {α < β | c(α, β) ≤ i}. We say that c is closed if Dc ≤i (β) is a closed subset of β for all β < κ and i < θ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [1]) Suppose that θ, χ < κ are regular cardinals. Any one of the following entails U(κ, κ, θ, χ). 1 There is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(≥ χ). 2 κ = λ+ and λ is regular. 3 κ = λ+ and cf(λ) = θ. 4 (κ) holds. Moreover, in all instances, U(κ, κ, θ, χ) is witnessed by a closed coloring.

Slide 46

Slide 46 text

Consistent failures of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Proposition (LH-Rinot, [1]) 1 If κ is weakly compact, then U(κ, 2, θ, 2) fails for all θ < κ.

Slide 47

Slide 47 text

Consistent failures of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Proposition (LH-Rinot, [1]) 1 If κ is weakly compact, then U(κ, 2, θ, 2) fails for all θ < κ. 2 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then U(λ+, 2, θ, cf(λ)+) fails for all regular θ ∈ λ+ \ {cf(λ)}

Slide 48

Slide 48 text

Consistent failures of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Proposition (LH-Rinot, [1]) 1 If κ is weakly compact, then U(κ, 2, θ, 2) fails for all θ < κ. 2 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then U(λ+, 2, θ, cf(λ)+) fails for all regular θ ∈ λ+ \ {cf(λ)} Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact.

Slide 49

Slide 49 text

Consistent failures of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Proposition (LH-Rinot, [1]) 1 If κ is weakly compact, then U(κ, 2, θ, 2) fails for all θ < κ. 2 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then U(λ+, 2, θ, cf(λ)+) fails for all regular θ ∈ λ+ \ {cf(λ)} Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact. • There is a forcing extension in which U(κ, κ, ω, ω) fails but κ is not weakly compact.

Slide 50

Slide 50 text

Consistent failures of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Proposition (LH-Rinot, [1]) 1 If κ is weakly compact, then U(κ, 2, θ, 2) fails for all θ < κ. 2 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then U(λ+, 2, θ, cf(λ)+) fails for all regular θ ∈ λ+ \ {cf(λ)} Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact. • There is a forcing extension in which U(κ, κ, ω, ω) fails but κ is not weakly compact. • For every infinite regular θ < κ, there is a forcing extension in which U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds for all χ < κ but U(κ, κ, θ , θ+) fails for all regular θ = θ.

Slide 51

Slide 51 text

Consistent failures of U(κ, µ, θ, χ) Proposition (LH-Rinot, [1]) 1 If κ is weakly compact, then U(κ, 2, θ, 2) fails for all θ < κ. 2 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then U(λ+, 2, θ, cf(λ)+) fails for all regular θ ∈ λ+ \ {cf(λ)} Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact. • There is a forcing extension in which U(κ, κ, ω, ω) fails but κ is not weakly compact. • For every infinite regular θ < κ, there is a forcing extension in which U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds for all χ < κ but U(κ, κ, θ , θ+) fails for all regular θ = θ. 2 If there is a supercompact cardinal, then there is a forcing extension in which U(ℵω+1, 2, ℵk , ℵ1) fails for all 1 ≤ k < ω.

Slide 52

Slide 52 text

Chapter 3 The C-sequence number

Slide 53

Slide 53 text

C-sequences and weak compactness Definition A C-sequence over κ is a sequence Cα | α < κ such that

Slide 54

Slide 54 text

C-sequences and weak compactness Definition A C-sequence over κ is a sequence Cα | α < κ such that • Cα is a club in α for all α ∈ lim(κ);

Slide 55

Slide 55 text

C-sequences and weak compactness Definition A C-sequence over κ is a sequence Cα | α < κ such that • Cα is a club in α for all α ∈ lim(κ); • Cα+1 = {α} for all α < κ.

Slide 56

Slide 56 text

C-sequences and weak compactness Definition A C-sequence over κ is a sequence Cα | α < κ such that • Cα is a club in α for all α ∈ lim(κ); • Cα+1 = {α} for all α < κ. Theorem (Todorcevic) For every regular, uncountable cardinal κ, the following are equivalent.

Slide 57

Slide 57 text

C-sequences and weak compactness Definition A C-sequence over κ is a sequence Cα | α < κ such that • Cα is a club in α for all α ∈ lim(κ); • Cα+1 = {α} for all α < κ. Theorem (Todorcevic) For every regular, uncountable cardinal κ, the following are equivalent. 1 κ is weakly compact.

Slide 58

Slide 58 text

C-sequences and weak compactness Definition A C-sequence over κ is a sequence Cα | α < κ such that • Cα is a club in α for all α ∈ lim(κ); • Cα+1 = {α} for all α < κ. Theorem (Todorcevic) For every regular, uncountable cardinal κ, the following are equivalent. 1 κ is weakly compact. 2 For every C-sequence Cα | α < κ , there is an unbounded D ⊆ κ such that, for every α < κ, there is β < κ for which D ∩ α = Cβ ∩ α.

Slide 59

Slide 59 text

The C-sequence number Motivated by Todorcevic’s characterization of weak compactness, we introduce the notion of the C-sequence number of a cardinal κ (denoted χ(κ)), which can be seen as measuring how far away κ is from being weakly compact.

Slide 60

Slide 60 text

The C-sequence number Motivated by Todorcevic’s characterization of weak compactness, we introduce the notion of the C-sequence number of a cardinal κ (denoted χ(κ)), which can be seen as measuring how far away κ is from being weakly compact. Definition (The C-sequence number) For every regular, uncountable cardinal κ, let χ(κ) = 0 if κ is weakly compact.

Slide 61

Slide 61 text

The C-sequence number Motivated by Todorcevic’s characterization of weak compactness, we introduce the notion of the C-sequence number of a cardinal κ (denoted χ(κ)), which can be seen as measuring how far away κ is from being weakly compact. Definition (The C-sequence number) For every regular, uncountable cardinal κ, let χ(κ) = 0 if κ is weakly compact. Otherwise, let χ(κ) be the least cardinal χ such that, for every C-sequence Cα | α < κ , there is an unbounded D ⊆ κ such that, for every α < κ, there is b ∈ [κ]χ for which D ∩ α ⊆ β∈b Cβ.

Slide 62

Slide 62 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ.

Slide 63

Slide 63 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ. 2 For every infinite cardinal λ, cf(λ) ≤ χ(λ+) ≤ λ.

Slide 64

Slide 64 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ. 2 For every infinite cardinal λ, cf(λ) ≤ χ(λ+) ≤ λ. In particular, if λ is regular, then χ(λ+) = λ.

Slide 65

Slide 65 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ. 2 For every infinite cardinal λ, cf(λ) ≤ χ(λ+) ≤ λ. In particular, if λ is regular, then χ(λ+) = λ. 3 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then χ(λ+) = cf(λ).

Slide 66

Slide 66 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ. 2 For every infinite cardinal λ, cf(λ) ≤ χ(λ+) ≤ λ. In particular, if λ is regular, then χ(λ+) = λ. 3 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then χ(λ+) = cf(λ). 4 If χ(κ) > 1, then χ(κ) ≥ ℵ0.

Slide 67

Slide 67 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ. 2 For every infinite cardinal λ, cf(λ) ≤ χ(λ+) ≤ λ. In particular, if λ is regular, then χ(λ+) = λ. 3 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then χ(λ+) = cf(λ). 4 If χ(κ) > 1, then χ(κ) ≥ ℵ0. 5 If χ(κ) = 1, then κ is greatly Mahlo.

Slide 68

Slide 68 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ. 2 For every infinite cardinal λ, cf(λ) ≤ χ(λ+) ≤ λ. In particular, if λ is regular, then χ(λ+) = λ. 3 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then χ(λ+) = cf(λ). 4 If χ(κ) > 1, then χ(κ) ≥ ℵ0. 5 If χ(κ) = 1, then κ is greatly Mahlo. 6 Every stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(> χ(κ)) reflects.

Slide 69

Slide 69 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ. 2 For every infinite cardinal λ, cf(λ) ≤ χ(λ+) ≤ λ. In particular, if λ is regular, then χ(λ+) = λ. 3 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then χ(λ+) = cf(λ). 4 If χ(κ) > 1, then χ(κ) ≥ ℵ0. 5 If χ(κ) = 1, then κ is greatly Mahlo. 6 Every stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(> χ(κ)) reflects. 7 If µ < κ and (κ, < µ) holds, then χ(κ) ≥ ℵ0.

Slide 70

Slide 70 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ. 2 For every infinite cardinal λ, cf(λ) ≤ χ(λ+) ≤ λ. In particular, if λ is regular, then χ(λ+) = λ. 3 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then χ(λ+) = cf(λ). 4 If χ(κ) > 1, then χ(κ) ≥ ℵ0. 5 If χ(κ) = 1, then κ is greatly Mahlo. 6 Every stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(> χ(κ)) reflects. 7 If µ < κ and (κ, < µ) holds, then χ(κ) ≥ ℵ0. 8 If (κ, < ω) holds, then χ(κ) is as large as possible.

Slide 71

Slide 71 text

Some basic facts Proposition The C-sequence number satisfies the following properties. 1 χ(κ) ≤ κ. 2 For every infinite cardinal λ, cf(λ) ≤ χ(λ+) ≤ λ. In particular, if λ is regular, then χ(λ+) = λ. 3 If λ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then χ(λ+) = cf(λ). 4 If χ(κ) > 1, then χ(κ) ≥ ℵ0. 5 If χ(κ) = 1, then κ is greatly Mahlo. 6 Every stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(> χ(κ)) reflects. 7 If µ < κ and (κ, < µ) holds, then χ(κ) ≥ ℵ0. 8 If (κ, < ω) holds, then χ(κ) is as large as possible. I.e., χ(κ) = sup(κ ∩ Reg).

Slide 72

Slide 72 text

Some consistency results Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact.

Slide 73

Slide 73 text

Some consistency results Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact. • There is a forcing extension in which χ(κ) = 1.

Slide 74

Slide 74 text

Some consistency results Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact. • There is a forcing extension in which χ(κ) = 1. • For every infinite regular θ < κ, there is a forcing extension in which χ(κ) = θ.

Slide 75

Slide 75 text

Some consistency results Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact. • There is a forcing extension in which χ(κ) = 1. • For every infinite regular θ < κ, there is a forcing extension in which χ(κ) = θ. 2 If there is a supercompact cardinal, then there is a forcing extension in which χ(ℵω+1) = ℵ0.

Slide 76

Slide 76 text

Some consistency results Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact. • There is a forcing extension in which χ(κ) = 1. • For every infinite regular θ < κ, there is a forcing extension in which χ(κ) = θ. 2 If there is a supercompact cardinal, then there is a forcing extension in which χ(ℵω+1) = ℵ0. Note the similarity to the previous consistency result about failures of U(κ, µ, θ, χ).

Slide 77

Slide 77 text

Some consistency results Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) 1 Suppose that κ is weakly compact. • There is a forcing extension in which U(κ, κ, ω, ω) fails but κ is not weakly compact. • For every infinite regular θ < κ, there is a forcing extension in which U(κ, κ, θ, χ) holds for all χ < κ but U(κ, κ, θ , θ+) fails for all regular θ = θ. 2 If there is a supercompact cardinal, then there is a forcing extension in which U(ℵω+1, 2, ℵk , ℵ1) fails for all 1 ≤ k < ω.

Slide 78

Slide 78 text

χ(κ) and closed colorings Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) Suppose that ℵ0 ≤ χ ≤ θ = cf(θ) < κ,

Slide 79

Slide 79 text

χ(κ) and closed colorings Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) Suppose that ℵ0 ≤ χ ≤ θ = cf(θ) < κ, and suppose that there is a closed witness to U(κ, 2, θ, χ).

Slide 80

Slide 80 text

χ(κ) and closed colorings Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) Suppose that ℵ0 ≤ χ ≤ θ = cf(θ) < κ, and suppose that there is a closed witness to U(κ, 2, θ, χ). Then χ(κ) ≥ χ.

Slide 81

Slide 81 text

χ(κ) and closed colorings Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) Suppose that ℵ0 ≤ χ ≤ θ = cf(θ) < κ, and suppose that there is a closed witness to U(κ, 2, θ, χ). Then χ(κ) ≥ χ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) There is a closed witness to U(κ, κ, ω, χ(κ)).

Slide 82

Slide 82 text

χ(κ) and closed colorings Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) Suppose that ℵ0 ≤ χ ≤ θ = cf(θ) < κ, and suppose that there is a closed witness to U(κ, 2, θ, χ). Then χ(κ) ≥ χ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) There is a closed witness to U(κ, κ, ω, χ(κ)). Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) There is a closed witness to U(κ, κ, χ(κ), χ(κ)).

Slide 83

Slide 83 text

χ(κ) and closed colorings Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) Suppose that ℵ0 ≤ χ ≤ θ = cf(θ) < κ, and suppose that there is a closed witness to U(κ, 2, θ, χ). Then χ(κ) ≥ χ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) There is a closed witness to U(κ, κ, ω, χ(κ)). Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) There is a closed witness to U(κ, κ, χ(κ), χ(κ)). Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) For infinite regular θ < κ, TFAE:

Slide 84

Slide 84 text

χ(κ) and closed colorings Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) Suppose that ℵ0 ≤ χ ≤ θ = cf(θ) < κ, and suppose that there is a closed witness to U(κ, 2, θ, χ). Then χ(κ) ≥ χ. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) There is a closed witness to U(κ, κ, ω, χ(κ)). Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) There is a closed witness to U(κ, κ, χ(κ), χ(κ)). Theorem (LH-Rinot, [2]) For infinite regular θ < κ, TFAE: 1 there is a C-sequence C over κ such that χ(C) = θ; 2 there is a closed witness to U(κ, κ, θ, θ).

Slide 85

Slide 85 text

Some conjectures Conjectures 1 For all regular θ < κ, U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds.

Slide 86

Slide 86 text

Some conjectures Conjectures 1 For all regular θ < κ, U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 2 (Slightly less ambitious) For all regular θ ≤ χ(κ), U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds.

Slide 87

Slide 87 text

Some conjectures Conjectures 1 For all regular θ < κ, U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 2 (Slightly less ambitious) For all regular θ ≤ χ(κ), U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 3 For all regular, uncountable κ, TFAE: • χ(κ) ≤ 1;

Slide 88

Slide 88 text

Some conjectures Conjectures 1 For all regular θ < κ, U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 2 (Slightly less ambitious) For all regular θ ≤ χ(κ), U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 3 For all regular, uncountable κ, TFAE: • χ(κ) ≤ 1; • the κ-Knaster property is ℵ0 -productive.

Slide 89

Slide 89 text

Some conjectures Conjectures 1 For all regular θ < κ, U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 2 (Slightly less ambitious) For all regular θ ≤ χ(κ), U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 3 For all regular, uncountable κ, TFAE: • χ(κ) ≤ 1; • the κ-Knaster property is ℵ0 -productive. 4 For all regular, uncountable κ, TFAE: • κ is weakly compact;

Slide 90

Slide 90 text

Some conjectures Conjectures 1 For all regular θ < κ, U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 2 (Slightly less ambitious) For all regular θ ≤ χ(κ), U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 3 For all regular, uncountable κ, TFAE: • χ(κ) ≤ 1; • the κ-Knaster property is ℵ0 -productive. 4 For all regular, uncountable κ, TFAE: • κ is weakly compact; • U(κ, 2, θ, 2) fails for all infinite regular θ < κ;

Slide 91

Slide 91 text

Some conjectures Conjectures 1 For all regular θ < κ, U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 2 (Slightly less ambitious) For all regular θ ≤ χ(κ), U(κ, κ, θ, χ(κ)) holds. 3 For all regular, uncountable κ, TFAE: • χ(κ) ≤ 1; • the κ-Knaster property is ℵ0 -productive. 4 For all regular, uncountable κ, TFAE: • κ is weakly compact; • U(κ, 2, θ, 2) fails for all infinite regular θ < κ; • U(κ, 2, ℵ0 , 2) fails.

Slide 92

Slide 92 text

Chapter 3 Subadditive colorings

Slide 93

Slide 93 text

Subadditivity Definition A coloring c : [κ]2 → θ is said to be subadditive if, for all α < β < γ < κ,

Slide 94

Slide 94 text

Subadditivity Definition A coloring c : [κ]2 → θ is said to be subadditive if, for all α < β < γ < κ, 1 c(α, γ) ≤ max{c(α, β), c(β, γ)};

Slide 95

Slide 95 text

Subadditivity Definition A coloring c : [κ]2 → θ is said to be subadditive if, for all α < β < γ < κ, 1 c(α, γ) ≤ max{c(α, β), c(β, γ)}; 2 c(α, β) ≤ max{c(α, γ), c(β, γ)}.

Slide 96

Slide 96 text

Subadditivity Definition A coloring c : [κ]2 → θ is said to be subadditive if, for all α < β < γ < κ, 1 c(α, γ) ≤ max{c(α, β), c(β, γ)}; 2 c(α, β) ≤ max{c(α, γ), c(β, γ)}. We say that c is subadditive of the first (resp. second) kind if it satisfies 1 (resp. 2).

Slide 97

Slide 97 text

Subadditivity Definition A coloring c : [κ]2 → θ is said to be subadditive if, for all α < β < γ < κ, 1 c(α, γ) ≤ max{c(α, β), c(β, γ)}; 2 c(α, β) ≤ max{c(α, γ), c(β, γ)}. We say that c is subadditive of the first (resp. second) kind if it satisfies 1 (resp. 2). Subadditive witnesses to U(κ, µ, θ, χ) are particularly useful in applications.

Slide 98

Slide 98 text

Subadditivity Definition A coloring c : [κ]2 → θ is said to be subadditive if, for all α < β < γ < κ, 1 c(α, γ) ≤ max{c(α, β), c(β, γ)}; 2 c(α, β) ≤ max{c(α, γ), c(β, γ)}. We say that c is subadditive of the first (resp. second) kind if it satisfies 1 (resp. 2). Subadditive witnesses to U(κ, µ, θ, χ) are particularly useful in applications. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [3]) Suppose that (κ) holds. Then, for every regular θ < κ, there is a subadditive witness to U(κ, κ, θ, χ) for all χ < κ.

Slide 99

Slide 99 text

Consistent negative results Subadditive witnesses to U(κ, λ, θ, χ) do not necessarily exist, though, even when U(κ, λ, θ, χ) holds.

Slide 100

Slide 100 text

Consistent negative results Subadditive witnesses to U(κ, λ, θ, χ) do not necessarily exist, though, even when U(κ, λ, θ, χ) holds. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [3]) If the P-ideal dichotomy holds, then, for every regular κ > ℵ1, there is no subadditive witness to U(κ, 2, ℵ0, 2).

Slide 101

Slide 101 text

Consistent negative results Subadditive witnesses to U(κ, λ, θ, χ) do not necessarily exist, though, even when U(κ, λ, θ, χ) holds. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [3]) If the P-ideal dichotomy holds, then, for every regular κ > ℵ1, there is no subadditive witness to U(κ, 2, ℵ0, 2). Theorem (Shani, ’16, LH, ’17) Relative to the consistency of large cardinals, there are consistently regular cardinals κ for which (κ, 2) holds but, for every regular θ < κ, there is no subadditive witness to U(κ, 2, θ, 2).

Slide 102

Slide 102 text

Consistent negative results Subadditive witnesses to U(κ, λ, θ, χ) do not necessarily exist, though, even when U(κ, λ, θ, χ) holds. Theorem (LH-Rinot, [3]) If the P-ideal dichotomy holds, then, for every regular κ > ℵ1, there is no subadditive witness to U(κ, 2, ℵ0, 2). Theorem (Shani, ’16, LH, ’17) Relative to the consistency of large cardinals, there are consistently regular cardinals κ for which (κ, 2) holds but, for every regular θ < κ, there is no subadditive witness to U(κ, 2, θ, 2). (Here κ can be arranged to be a successor of a regular cardinal, a successor of a singular cardinal, or an inaccessible cardinal.)

Slide 103

Slide 103 text

Tightness of Gδ-modifications Definition Let X be a topological space.

Slide 104

Slide 104 text

Tightness of Gδ-modifications Definition Let X be a topological space. 1 The tightness of X, denoted t(X), is the least cardinal κ such that, for every T ⊆ X and every x ∈ cl(T), there is T ∈ [T]≤κ such that x ∈ cl(T ).

Slide 105

Slide 105 text

Tightness of Gδ-modifications Definition Let X be a topological space. 1 The tightness of X, denoted t(X), is the least cardinal κ such that, for every T ⊆ X and every x ∈ cl(T), there is T ∈ [T]≤κ such that x ∈ cl(T ). 2 X is Fr´ echet if for every T ⊆ X and every x ∈ cl(T), there is a (countable) sequence of elements of T converging to x.

Slide 106

Slide 106 text

Tightness of Gδ-modifications Definition Let X be a topological space. 1 The tightness of X, denoted t(X), is the least cardinal κ such that, for every T ⊆ X and every x ∈ cl(T), there is T ∈ [T]≤κ such that x ∈ cl(T ). 2 X is Fr´ echet if for every T ⊆ X and every x ∈ cl(T), there is a (countable) sequence of elements of T converging to x. Note that, if X is Fr´ echet, then t(X) ≤ ℵ0.

Slide 107

Slide 107 text

Tightness of Gδ-modifications Definition Let X be a topological space. 1 The tightness of X, denoted t(X), is the least cardinal κ such that, for every T ⊆ X and every x ∈ cl(T), there is T ∈ [T]≤κ such that x ∈ cl(T ). 2 X is Fr´ echet if for every T ⊆ X and every x ∈ cl(T), there is a (countable) sequence of elements of T converging to x. Note that, if X is Fr´ echet, then t(X) ≤ ℵ0. 3 The Gδ-modification of X, denoted Xδ, is the space with the same underlying set whose topology is generated by the Gδ sets of X.

Slide 108

Slide 108 text

Tightness of Gδ-modifications Definition Let X be a topological space. 1 The tightness of X, denoted t(X), is the least cardinal κ such that, for every T ⊆ X and every x ∈ cl(T), there is T ∈ [T]≤κ such that x ∈ cl(T ). 2 X is Fr´ echet if for every T ⊆ X and every x ∈ cl(T), there is a (countable) sequence of elements of T converging to x. Note that, if X is Fr´ echet, then t(X) ≤ ℵ0. 3 The Gδ-modification of X, denoted Xδ, is the space with the same underlying set whose topology is generated by the Gδ sets of X. Some recent work has been done studying the relationship between t(X) and t(Xδ). Of particular interest is whether there is an upper bound on t(Xδ) for countably tight (or stronger) spaces X.

Slide 109

Slide 109 text

Some results Theorem (Dow-Juh´ asz-Soukup-Szentmikl´ ossy-Weiss, ’19) If there is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(ω), then there is a Fr´ echet space X such that t(Xδ) = κ.

Slide 110

Slide 110 text

Some results Theorem (Dow-Juh´ asz-Soukup-Szentmikl´ ossy-Weiss, ’19) If there is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(ω), then there is a Fr´ echet space X such that t(Xδ) = κ. Theorem (DHSSW, ’19) If λ is strongly compact and t(X) < λ, then t(Xδ) ≤ λ.

Slide 111

Slide 111 text

Some results Theorem (Dow-Juh´ asz-Soukup-Szentmikl´ ossy-Weiss, ’19) If there is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(ω), then there is a Fr´ echet space X such that t(Xδ) = κ. Theorem (DHSSW, ’19) If λ is strongly compact and t(X) < λ, then t(Xδ) ≤ λ. Theorem (Chen-Mertens–Szeptycki, ’2X) If (κ) holds, then there is a Fr´ echet α1-space X such that t(Xδ) = κ.

Slide 112

Slide 112 text

Some results Theorem (Dow-Juh´ asz-Soukup-Szentmikl´ ossy-Weiss, ’19) If there is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(ω), then there is a Fr´ echet space X such that t(Xδ) = κ. Theorem (DHSSW, ’19) If λ is strongly compact and t(X) < λ, then t(Xδ) ≤ λ. Theorem (Chen-Mertens–Szeptycki, ’2X) If there is a subadditive witness to U(κ, 2, ℵ0, 2), then there is a Fr´ echet α1-space X such that t(Xδ) = κ.

Slide 113

Slide 113 text

Some results Theorem (Dow-Juh´ asz-Soukup-Szentmikl´ ossy-Weiss, ’19) If there is a non-reflecting stationary subset of κ ∩ cof(ω), then there is a Fr´ echet space X such that t(Xδ) = κ. Theorem (DHSSW, ’19) If λ is strongly compact and t(X) < λ, then t(Xδ) ≤ λ. Theorem (Chen-Mertens–Szeptycki, ’2X) If there is a subadditive witness to U(κ, 2, ℵ0, 2), then there is a Fr´ echet α1-space X such that t(Xδ) = κ. Theorem (Chen-Mertens–Szeptycki, ’2X) If PID holds and X is a Fr´ echet α1-space, then t(Xδ) ≤ ℵ1.

Slide 114

Slide 114 text

An example from a failure of SCH Theorem (LH-Rinot, [3]) Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal of countable cofinality and SCH fails at µ. Then there is a Fr´ echet α1-space X such that t(Xδ) = µ+.

Slide 115

Slide 115 text

An example from a failure of SCH Theorem (LH-Rinot, [3]) Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal of countable cofinality and SCH fails at µ. Then there is a Fr´ echet α1-space X such that t(Xδ) = µ+. We’ll end by sketching a proof of this theorem.

Slide 116

Slide 116 text

An example from a failure of SCH Theorem (LH-Rinot, [3]) Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal of countable cofinality and SCH fails at µ. Then there is a Fr´ echet α1-space X such that t(Xδ) = µ+. We’ll end by sketching a proof of this theorem. Lemma (folklore) For every infinite cardinal µ, there is a witness c to U(µ+, 2, cf(µ), 2) such that

Slide 117

Slide 117 text

An example from a failure of SCH Theorem (LH-Rinot, [3]) Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal of countable cofinality and SCH fails at µ. Then there is a Fr´ echet α1-space X such that t(Xδ) = µ+. We’ll end by sketching a proof of this theorem. Lemma (folklore) For every infinite cardinal µ, there is a witness c to U(µ+, 2, cf(µ), 2) such that • c is subadditive of the first kind;

Slide 118

Slide 118 text

An example from a failure of SCH Theorem (LH-Rinot, [3]) Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal of countable cofinality and SCH fails at µ. Then there is a Fr´ echet α1-space X such that t(Xδ) = µ+. We’ll end by sketching a proof of this theorem. Lemma (folklore) For every infinite cardinal µ, there is a witness c to U(µ+, 2, cf(µ), 2) such that • c is subadditive of the first kind; • c is locally small, i.e., |Dc ≤i (β)| < µ for all i < cf(µ) and all β < µ+.

Slide 119

Slide 119 text

Proof sketch Fix a coloring c : [µ+]2 → ω as in the Lemma.

Slide 120

Slide 120 text

Proof sketch Fix a coloring c : [µ+]2 → ω as in the Lemma. The underlying set of X will be µ+ ∪ {∞}.

Slide 121

Slide 121 text

Proof sketch Fix a coloring c : [µ+]2 → ω as in the Lemma. The underlying set of X will be µ+ ∪ {∞}. Every element of µ+ is isolated in X.

Slide 122

Slide 122 text

Proof sketch Fix a coloring c : [µ+]2 → ω as in the Lemma. The underlying set of X will be µ+ ∪ {∞}. Every element of µ+ is isolated in X. Basic open neighborhoods of ∞ in X are of the form Ni,β := {∞} ∪ (µ+ \ Dc ≤i (β)),

Slide 123

Slide 123 text

Proof sketch Fix a coloring c : [µ+]2 → ω as in the Lemma. The underlying set of X will be µ+ ∪ {∞}. Every element of µ+ is isolated in X. Basic open neighborhoods of ∞ in X are of the form Ni,β := {∞} ∪ (µ+ \ Dc ≤i (β)), i.e., the closed subsets of µ+ are precisely the intersections of the sets Dc ≤i (β), so, if T ⊆ µ+, then ∞ ∈ cl(T) ⇔ ( ∃(i, β) ∈ ω × µ+)(T ⊆ Dc ≤i (β))

Slide 124

Slide 124 text

X is Fr´ echet Suppose that T ⊆ µ+ and ∞ ∈ cl(T).

Slide 125

Slide 125 text

X is Fr´ echet Suppose that T ⊆ µ+ and ∞ ∈ cl(T). Suppose first that |T| < µ. For each β > sup(T) + 1, define fβ : T → ω by fβ(α) := c(α, β).

Slide 126

Slide 126 text

X is Fr´ echet Suppose that T ⊆ µ+ and ∞ ∈ cl(T). Suppose first that |T| < µ. For each β > sup(T) + 1, define fβ : T → ω by fβ(α) := c(α, β). Since µ is strong limit, there are an unbounded A ⊆ µ+ and a function f : T → ω such that fβ = f for all β ∈ A.

Slide 127

Slide 127 text

X is Fr´ echet Suppose that T ⊆ µ+ and ∞ ∈ cl(T). Suppose first that |T| < µ. For each β > sup(T) + 1, define fβ : T → ω by fβ(α) := c(α, β). Since µ is strong limit, there are an unbounded A ⊆ µ+ and a function f : T → ω such that fβ = f for all β ∈ A. Since ∞ ∈ cl(T), for each i < ω, we can fix αi ∈ T such that f (αi ) ≥ i.

Slide 128

Slide 128 text

X is Fr´ echet Suppose that T ⊆ µ+ and ∞ ∈ cl(T). Suppose first that |T| < µ. For each β > sup(T) + 1, define fβ : T → ω by fβ(α) := c(α, β). Since µ is strong limit, there are an unbounded A ⊆ µ+ and a function f : T → ω such that fβ = f for all β ∈ A. Since ∞ ∈ cl(T), for each i < ω, we can fix αi ∈ T such that f (αi ) ≥ i. Then every Dc ≤i (β) contains only finitely many of the αi ’s, so αi | i < ω converges to ∞.

Slide 129

Slide 129 text

X is Fr´ echet Suppose that T ⊆ µ+ and ∞ ∈ cl(T). Suppose first that |T| < µ. For each β > sup(T) + 1, define fβ : T → ω by fβ(α) := c(α, β). Since µ is strong limit, there are an unbounded A ⊆ µ+ and a function f : T → ω such that fβ = f for all β ∈ A. Since ∞ ∈ cl(T), for each i < ω, we can fix αi ∈ T such that f (αi ) ≥ i. Then every Dc ≤i (β) contains only finitely many of the αi ’s, so αi | i < ω converges to ∞. Suppose now that |T| ≥ µ.

Slide 130

Slide 130 text

X is Fr´ echet Suppose that T ⊆ µ+ and ∞ ∈ cl(T). Suppose first that |T| < µ. For each β > sup(T) + 1, define fβ : T → ω by fβ(α) := c(α, β). Since µ is strong limit, there are an unbounded A ⊆ µ+ and a function f : T → ω such that fβ = f for all β ∈ A. Since ∞ ∈ cl(T), for each i < ω, we can fix αi ∈ T such that f (αi ) ≥ i. Then every Dc ≤i (β) contains only finitely many of the αi ’s, so αi | i < ω converges to ∞. Suppose now that |T| ≥ µ. For each (i, β), we have |Dc ≤i (β)| < µ, so |[Dc ≤i (β)]ℵ0 | < µ.

Slide 131

Slide 131 text

X is Fr´ echet Suppose that T ⊆ µ+ and ∞ ∈ cl(T). Suppose first that |T| < µ. For each β > sup(T) + 1, define fβ : T → ω by fβ(α) := c(α, β). Since µ is strong limit, there are an unbounded A ⊆ µ+ and a function f : T → ω such that fβ = f for all β ∈ A. Since ∞ ∈ cl(T), for each i < ω, we can fix αi ∈ T such that f (αi ) ≥ i. Then every Dc ≤i (β) contains only finitely many of the αi ’s, so αi | i < ω converges to ∞. Suppose now that |T| ≥ µ. For each (i, β), we have |Dc ≤i (β)| < µ, so |[Dc ≤i (β)]ℵ0 | < µ. Therefore, the number of elements of [T]ℵ0 that are contained in some Dc ≤i (β) is at most µ+.

Slide 132

Slide 132 text

X is Fr´ echet Suppose that T ⊆ µ+ and ∞ ∈ cl(T). Suppose first that |T| < µ. For each β > sup(T) + 1, define fβ : T → ω by fβ(α) := c(α, β). Since µ is strong limit, there are an unbounded A ⊆ µ+ and a function f : T → ω such that fβ = f for all β ∈ A. Since ∞ ∈ cl(T), for each i < ω, we can fix αi ∈ T such that f (αi ) ≥ i. Then every Dc ≤i (β) contains only finitely many of the αi ’s, so αi | i < ω converges to ∞. Suppose now that |T| ≥ µ. For each (i, β), we have |Dc ≤i (β)| < µ, so |[Dc ≤i (β)]ℵ0 | < µ. Therefore, the number of elements of [T]ℵ0 that are contained in some Dc ≤i (β) is at most µ+. Since SCH fails at µ, |[T]ℵ0 | > µ+, so we can find a countable subset of T that is not contained in any Dc ≤i (β), and proceed as in the previous case.

Slide 133

Slide 133 text

t(Xδ ) = µ+ In X, every closed subset of µ+ is bounded in µ+.

Slide 134

Slide 134 text

t(Xδ ) = µ+ In X, every closed subset of µ+ is bounded in µ+. Since every closed subset of µ+ in Xδ is contained in a countable union of closed subsets of µ+ in X, this is also true in Xδ.

Slide 135

Slide 135 text

t(Xδ ) = µ+ In X, every closed subset of µ+ is bounded in µ+. Since every closed subset of µ+ in Xδ is contained in a countable union of closed subsets of µ+ in X, this is also true in Xδ. In particular, in Xδ, ∞ ∈ cl(µ+).

Slide 136

Slide 136 text

t(Xδ ) = µ+ In X, every closed subset of µ+ is bounded in µ+. Since every closed subset of µ+ in Xδ is contained in a countable union of closed subsets of µ+ in X, this is also true in Xδ. In particular, in Xδ, ∞ ∈ cl(µ+). However, for every β < µ+, we have β = i<ω Dc ≤i (β).

Slide 137

Slide 137 text

t(Xδ ) = µ+ In X, every closed subset of µ+ is bounded in µ+. Since every closed subset of µ+ in Xδ is contained in a countable union of closed subsets of µ+ in X, this is also true in Xδ. In particular, in Xδ, ∞ ∈ cl(µ+). However, for every β < µ+, we have β = i<ω Dc ≤i (β). Since Dc ≤i (β) is closed in X, β is closed in Xδ.

Slide 138

Slide 138 text

t(Xδ ) = µ+ In X, every closed subset of µ+ is bounded in µ+. Since every closed subset of µ+ in Xδ is contained in a countable union of closed subsets of µ+ in X, this is also true in Xδ. In particular, in Xδ, ∞ ∈ cl(µ+). However, for every β < µ+, we have β = i<ω Dc ≤i (β). Since Dc ≤i (β) is closed in X, β is closed in Xδ. Therefore, ∞ is not in the closure of any bounded subset of µ+ in Xδ.

Slide 139

Slide 139 text

t(Xδ ) = µ+ In X, every closed subset of µ+ is bounded in µ+. Since every closed subset of µ+ in Xδ is contained in a countable union of closed subsets of µ+ in X, this is also true in Xδ. In particular, in Xδ, ∞ ∈ cl(µ+). However, for every β < µ+, we have β = i<ω Dc ≤i (β). Since Dc ≤i (β) is closed in X, β is closed in Xδ. Therefore, ∞ is not in the closure of any bounded subset of µ+ in Xδ. It follows that t(Xδ) = µ+.

Slide 140

Slide 140 text

All artwork by Vera Moln´ ar.

Slide 141

Slide 141 text

Thank you!