Slide 1

Slide 1 text

The Continuum Hypothesis, the Axiom of Choice, and Lebesgue Measurability Chris Lambie-Hanson CMU Graduate Student Seminar 11 October 2011

Slide 2

Slide 2 text

Definitions If S is a set, then a linear order on S is a binary relation ≤ such that

Slide 3

Slide 3 text

Definitions If S is a set, then a linear order on S is a binary relation ≤ such that 1 For all x ∈ S, x ≤ x.

Slide 4

Slide 4 text

Definitions If S is a set, then a linear order on S is a binary relation ≤ such that 1 For all x ∈ S, x ≤ x. 2 For all x, y ∈ S, if x ≤ y and y ≤ x, then x = y.

Slide 5

Slide 5 text

Definitions If S is a set, then a linear order on S is a binary relation ≤ such that 1 For all x ∈ S, x ≤ x. 2 For all x, y ∈ S, if x ≤ y and y ≤ x, then x = y. 3 For all x, y, z ∈ S, if x ≤ y and y ≤ z, then x ≤ z.

Slide 6

Slide 6 text

Definitions If S is a set, then a linear order on S is a binary relation ≤ such that 1 For all x ∈ S, x ≤ x. 2 For all x, y ∈ S, if x ≤ y and y ≤ x, then x = y. 3 For all x, y, z ∈ S, if x ≤ y and y ≤ z, then x ≤ z. 4 For all x, y ∈ S, x ≤ y or y ≤ x.

Slide 7

Slide 7 text

Definitions If S is a set, then a linear order on S is a binary relation ≤ such that 1 For all x ∈ S, x ≤ x. 2 For all x, y ∈ S, if x ≤ y and y ≤ x, then x = y. 3 For all x, y, z ∈ S, if x ≤ y and y ≤ z, then x ≤ z. 4 For all x, y ∈ S, x ≤ y or y ≤ x. A linear order ≤ on a set S is a well-order if, for every nonempty X ⊆ S, there is a ≤-least element in X, i.e. there is x ∈ X such that, for all y ∈ X, x ≤ y.

Slide 8

Slide 8 text

The Axiom of Choice The Axiom of Choice is the assertion: For every family of nonempty sets F, there is a function g such that dom(g) = F and, for every X ∈ F, g(X) ∈ X.

Slide 9

Slide 9 text

The Axiom of Choice The Axiom of Choice is the assertion: For every family of nonempty sets F, there is a function g such that dom(g) = F and, for every X ∈ F, g(X) ∈ X. The Axiom of Choice is equivalent to the Well-ordering Theorem, which asserts that every set can be well-ordered.

Slide 10

Slide 10 text

Ordinals, Informally An ordinal number describes the order type of a well-ordering.

Slide 11

Slide 11 text

Ordinals, Informally An ordinal number describes the order type of a well-ordering. • A natural number n is an ordinal describing a well-ordering with n elements.

Slide 12

Slide 12 text

Ordinals, Informally An ordinal number describes the order type of a well-ordering. • A natural number n is an ordinal describing a well-ordering with n elements. • The ordinal describing the order type of the natural numbers is ω.

Slide 13

Slide 13 text

Ordinals, Informally An ordinal number describes the order type of a well-ordering. • A natural number n is an ordinal describing a well-ordering with n elements. • The ordinal describing the order type of the natural numbers is ω. • The ordinal describing the order type of the natural numbers plus one element larger than all of the natural numbers is ω + 1.

Slide 14

Slide 14 text

Ordinals, Informally An ordinal number describes the order type of a well-ordering. • A natural number n is an ordinal describing a well-ordering with n elements. • The ordinal describing the order type of the natural numbers is ω. • The ordinal describing the order type of the natural numbers plus one element larger than all of the natural numbers is ω + 1. An ordinal α is actually a set of ordinals, well-ordered by ∈, of order-type α.

Slide 15

Slide 15 text

Ordinals, Informally An ordinal number describes the order type of a well-ordering. • A natural number n is an ordinal describing a well-ordering with n elements. • The ordinal describing the order type of the natural numbers is ω. • The ordinal describing the order type of the natural numbers plus one element larger than all of the natural numbers is ω + 1. An ordinal α is actually a set of ordinals, well-ordered by ∈, of order-type α. If α = β + 1 = β ∪ {β}, then α is called a successor ordinal. Otherwise, it is called a limit ordinal.

Slide 16

Slide 16 text

Cardinals Two sets A and B have the same cardinality if there is a bijection f : A → B.

Slide 17

Slide 17 text

Cardinals Two sets A and B have the same cardinality if there is a bijection f : A → B. The cardinality of A, written |A|, can be thought of as the equivalence class of all sets for which bijections with A exist.

Slide 18

Slide 18 text

Cardinals Two sets A and B have the same cardinality if there is a bijection f : A → B. The cardinality of A, written |A|, can be thought of as the equivalence class of all sets for which bijections with A exist. For two sets A and B, we say |A| |B| if there is an injective function f : A → B.

Slide 19

Slide 19 text

Cardinals Two sets A and B have the same cardinality if there is a bijection f : A → B. The cardinality of A, written |A|, can be thought of as the equivalence class of all sets for which bijections with A exist. For two sets A and B, we say |A| |B| if there is an injective function f : A → B. Under the Axiom of Choice, a cardinality is often identified with the smallest ordinal of that cardinality. Thus, under AC, cardinalities are well-ordered by .

Slide 20

Slide 20 text

Cardinals Two sets A and B have the same cardinality if there is a bijection f : A → B. The cardinality of A, written |A|, can be thought of as the equivalence class of all sets for which bijections with A exist. For two sets A and B, we say |A| |B| if there is an injective function f : A → B. Under the Axiom of Choice, a cardinality is often identified with the smallest ordinal of that cardinality. Thus, under AC, cardinalities are well-ordered by . If α is an ordinal, the α-th infinite cardinal is written ℵα. The smallest ordinal of cardinality ℵα is written ωα.

Slide 21

Slide 21 text

Cardinals A set is called countable if it is either finite or has the same cardinality as the set of natural numbers.

Slide 22

Slide 22 text

Cardinals A set is called countable if it is either finite or has the same cardinality as the set of natural numbers. Every natural number n is a cardinal number.

Slide 23

Slide 23 text

Cardinals A set is called countable if it is either finite or has the same cardinality as the set of natural numbers. Every natural number n is a cardinal number. ω0 = ω, and |ω| = ℵ0.

Slide 24

Slide 24 text

Cardinals A set is called countable if it is either finite or has the same cardinality as the set of natural numbers. Every natural number n is a cardinal number. ω0 = ω, and |ω| = ℵ0. ω1 is the set of all countable ordinals, and |ω1| = ℵ1.

Slide 25

Slide 25 text

Cardinals A set is called countable if it is either finite or has the same cardinality as the set of natural numbers. Every natural number n is a cardinal number. ω0 = ω, and |ω| = ℵ0. ω1 is the set of all countable ordinals, and |ω1| = ℵ1. ω2 is the set of all ordinals of cardinality ≤ ℵ1, and |ω2| = ℵ2.

Slide 26

Slide 26 text

Cantor’s Theorem If A is a set, then the power set of A, written P(A), is the set of all subsets of A.

Slide 27

Slide 27 text

Cantor’s Theorem If A is a set, then the power set of A, written P(A), is the set of all subsets of A. Theorem For every set A, |A| ≺ |P(A)|.

Slide 28

Slide 28 text

Cantor’s Theorem If A is a set, then the power set of A, written P(A), is the set of all subsets of A. Theorem For every set A, |A| ≺ |P(A)|. It is clear that |A| |P(A)|, so it suffices to prove that there is no bijection f : A → P(A).

Slide 29

Slide 29 text

Hypergame We say a finite game is a two-player game with alternating moves which is guaranteed to end in a finite number of moves.

Slide 30

Slide 30 text

Hypergame We say a finite game is a two-player game with alternating moves which is guaranteed to end in a finite number of moves. Hypergame is a two-player game with alternating moves played as follows:

Slide 31

Slide 31 text

Hypergame We say a finite game is a two-player game with alternating moves which is guaranteed to end in a finite number of moves. Hypergame is a two-player game with alternating moves played as follows: 1 Player 1 names a finite game.

Slide 32

Slide 32 text

Hypergame We say a finite game is a two-player game with alternating moves which is guaranteed to end in a finite number of moves. Hypergame is a two-player game with alternating moves played as follows: 1 Player 1 names a finite game. 2 Player 2 makes the first move in that finite game.

Slide 33

Slide 33 text

Hypergame We say a finite game is a two-player game with alternating moves which is guaranteed to end in a finite number of moves. Hypergame is a two-player game with alternating moves played as follows: 1 Player 1 names a finite game. 2 Player 2 makes the first move in that finite game. 3 The players continue playing that finite game until it ends.

Slide 34

Slide 34 text

Hypergame Example:

Slide 35

Slide 35 text

Hypergame Example: I: “Let’s play chess!”

Slide 36

Slide 36 text

Hypergame Example: I: “Let’s play chess!” II:f3

Slide 37

Slide 37 text

Hypergame Example: I: “Let’s play chess!” II:f3 I: e6

Slide 38

Slide 38 text

Hypergame Example: I: “Let’s play chess!” II:f3 I: e6 II:g4

Slide 39

Slide 39 text

Hypergame Example: I: “Let’s play chess!” II:f3 I: e6 II:g4 I: Qh4#

Slide 40

Slide 40 text

Hypergame Is Hypergame a finite game?

Slide 41

Slide 41 text

Hypergame Is Hypergame a finite game? Clearly, yes, but...

Slide 42

Slide 42 text

Hypergame Is Hypergame a finite game? Clearly, yes, but... I: “Let’s play hypergame!”

Slide 43

Slide 43 text

Hypergame Is Hypergame a finite game? Clearly, yes, but... I: “Let’s play hypergame!” II:“Let’s play hypergame!”

Slide 44

Slide 44 text

Hypergame Is Hypergame a finite game? Clearly, yes, but... I: “Let’s play hypergame!” II:“Let’s play hypergame!” I: “Let’s play hypergame!”

Slide 45

Slide 45 text

Hypergame Is Hypergame a finite game? Clearly, yes, but... I: “Let’s play hypergame!” II:“Let’s play hypergame!” I: “Let’s play hypergame!” II:“Let’s play hypergame!” . . .

Slide 46

Slide 46 text

Proof of Cantor’s Theorem

Slide 47

Slide 47 text

Proof of Cantor’s Theorem Suppose for sake of contradiction that there is an infinite set A and a bijection f : A → P(A).

Slide 48

Slide 48 text

Proof of Cantor’s Theorem Suppose for sake of contradiction that there is an infinite set A and a bijection f : A → P(A). We say that (a0, a1, a2, . . .) is a path in A if: 1 a0 ∈ A 2 For all n, an+1 ∈ f (an)

Slide 49

Slide 49 text

Proof of Cantor’s Theorem Suppose for sake of contradiction that there is an infinite set A and a bijection f : A → P(A). We say that (a0, a1, a2, . . .) is a path in A if: 1 a0 ∈ A 2 For all n, an+1 ∈ f (an) Let X = {a ∈ A | there is no infinite path in A starting with a}.

Slide 50

Slide 50 text

Proof of Cantor’s Theorem Suppose for sake of contradiction that there is an infinite set A and a bijection f : A → P(A). We say that (a0, a1, a2, . . .) is a path in A if: 1 a0 ∈ A 2 For all n, an+1 ∈ f (an) Let X = {a ∈ A | there is no infinite path in A starting with a}. Since f is a bijection, there is x ∈ A such that f (x) = X.

Slide 51

Slide 51 text

Proof of Cantor’s Theorem Suppose for sake of contradiction that there is an infinite set A and a bijection f : A → P(A). We say that (a0, a1, a2, . . .) is a path in A if: 1 a0 ∈ A 2 For all n, an+1 ∈ f (an) Let X = {a ∈ A | there is no infinite path in A starting with a}. Since f is a bijection, there is x ∈ A such that f (x) = X. There can be no infinite path in A starting with x, as the second element of such a path would have to be in X. Thus, x ∈ f (x).

Slide 52

Slide 52 text

Proof of Cantor’s Theorem Suppose for sake of contradiction that there is an infinite set A and a bijection f : A → P(A). We say that (a0, a1, a2, . . .) is a path in A if: 1 a0 ∈ A 2 For all n, an+1 ∈ f (an) Let X = {a ∈ A | there is no infinite path in A starting with a}. Since f is a bijection, there is x ∈ A such that f (x) = X. There can be no infinite path in A starting with x, as the second element of such a path would have to be in X. Thus, x ∈ f (x). But then (x, x, x, . . .) is an infinite path in A starting with x. Contradiction.

Slide 53

Slide 53 text

Real numbers

Slide 54

Slide 54 text

Real numbers Definition A Polish space is a separable, completely metrizable topological space.

Slide 55

Slide 55 text

Real numbers Definition A Polish space is a separable, completely metrizable topological space. Fact There is a Borel isomorphism between any two uncountable Polish spaces.

Slide 56

Slide 56 text

Real numbers Definition A Polish space is a separable, completely metrizable topological space. Fact There is a Borel isomorphism between any two uncountable Polish spaces. Examples R, [0, 1], P(ω), ω2 = {countable infinite sequences of 0s and 1s}, ωω = {countable infinite sequences of natural numbers}

Slide 57

Slide 57 text

Real numbers Definition A Polish space is a separable, completely metrizable topological space. Fact There is a Borel isomorphism between any two uncountable Polish spaces. Examples R, [0, 1], P(ω), ω2 = {countable infinite sequences of 0s and 1s}, ωω = {countable infinite sequences of natural numbers} The cardinality of each of these examples is c = 2ℵ0 .

Slide 58

Slide 58 text

The Continuum Hypothesis CH: 2ℵ0 = ℵ1.

Slide 59

Slide 59 text

The Continuum Hypothesis CH: 2ℵ0 = ℵ1. Alternative formulations:

Slide 60

Slide 60 text

The Continuum Hypothesis CH: 2ℵ0 = ℵ1. Alternative formulations: • There is a surjection f : ω1 → R.

Slide 61

Slide 61 text

The Continuum Hypothesis CH: 2ℵ0 = ℵ1. Alternative formulations: • There is a surjection f : ω1 → R. • There is an injection g : R → ω1.

Slide 62

Slide 62 text

The Continuum Hypothesis CH: 2ℵ0 = ℵ1. Alternative formulations: • There is a surjection f : ω1 → R. • There is an injection g : R → ω1. • Every uncountable subset of R has cardinality 2ℵ0 .

Slide 63

Slide 63 text

The Continuum Hypothesis CH: 2ℵ0 = ℵ1. Alternative formulations: • There is a surjection f : ω1 → R. • There is an injection g : R → ω1. • Every uncountable subset of R has cardinality 2ℵ0 . Hilbert’s 1st problem.

Slide 64

Slide 64 text

Cantor-Bendixson Theorem

Slide 65

Slide 65 text

Cantor-Bendixson Theorem Definition If X is a topological space, then a set S ⊆ X is a perfect set if it is closed and has no isolated points.

Slide 66

Slide 66 text

Cantor-Bendixson Theorem Definition If X is a topological space, then a set S ⊆ X is a perfect set if it is closed and has no isolated points. Fact If S is a nonempty perfect subset of a Polish space, then |S| = 2ℵ0 .

Slide 67

Slide 67 text

Cantor-Bendixson Theorem Definition If X is a topological space, then a set S ⊆ X is a perfect set if it is closed and has no isolated points. Fact If S is a nonempty perfect subset of a Polish space, then |S| = 2ℵ0 . Definition A subset A of a Polish space has the perfect set property if either A is countable or A contains a nonempty perfect subset.

Slide 68

Slide 68 text

Cantor-Bendixson Theorem Definition If X is a topological space, then a set S ⊆ X is a perfect set if it is closed and has no isolated points. Fact If S is a nonempty perfect subset of a Polish space, then |S| = 2ℵ0 . Definition A subset A of a Polish space has the perfect set property if either A is countable or A contains a nonempty perfect subset. Theorem If X is a Polish space, then every closed set C ⊆ X can be written uniquely as the disjoint union of a perfect set and a countable set.

Slide 69

Slide 69 text

Cantor-Bendixson Theorem Definition If X is a topological space, then a set S ⊆ X is a perfect set if it is closed and has no isolated points. Fact If S is a nonempty perfect subset of a Polish space, then |S| = 2ℵ0 . Definition A subset A of a Polish space has the perfect set property if either A is countable or A contains a nonempty perfect subset. Theorem If X is a Polish space, then every closed set C ⊆ X can be written uniquely as the disjoint union of a perfect set and a countable set. Corollary For every uncountable closed set C ⊆ R, |C| = 2ℵ0 .

Slide 70

Slide 70 text

G˝ odel’s Constructible Universe The constructible universe, denoted L, was introduced by Kurt G˝ odel in 1938. It is a model of ZFC.

Slide 71

Slide 71 text

G˝ odel’s Constructible Universe The constructible universe, denoted L, was introduced by Kurt G˝ odel in 1938. It is a model of ZFC. L is, in a sense, the smallest model of ZFC containing all of the ordinals.

Slide 72

Slide 72 text

G˝ odel’s Constructible Universe The constructible universe, denoted L, was introduced by Kurt G˝ odel in 1938. It is a model of ZFC. L is, in a sense, the smallest model of ZFC containing all of the ordinals. CH is true in L.

Slide 73

Slide 73 text

G˝ odel’s Constructible Universe The constructible universe, denoted L, was introduced by Kurt G˝ odel in 1938. It is a model of ZFC. L is, in a sense, the smallest model of ZFC containing all of the ordinals. CH is true in L. Shelah: “L looks like the head of a gay chapter of the Ku Klux Klan - a case worthy of study, but probably not representative.”

Slide 74

Slide 74 text

Forcing

Slide 75

Slide 75 text

Forcing In 1963, Paul Cohen introduced the technique of forcing, which allows for the construction of new models of ZFC.

Slide 76

Slide 76 text

Forcing In 1963, Paul Cohen introduced the technique of forcing, which allows for the construction of new models of ZFC. ”Adding sets, but very gently.”

Slide 77

Slide 77 text

Forcing In 1963, Paul Cohen introduced the technique of forcing, which allows for the construction of new models of ZFC. ”Adding sets, but very gently.” Cohen used forcing to construct a model of ZFC in which CH is false by adding ℵ2-many new subsets of ω.

Slide 78

Slide 78 text

Forcing In 1963, Paul Cohen introduced the technique of forcing, which allows for the construction of new models of ZFC. ”Adding sets, but very gently.” Cohen used forcing to construct a model of ZFC in which CH is false by adding ℵ2-many new subsets of ω. This “settled” Hilbert’s first problem.

Slide 79

Slide 79 text

The Axiom of Symmetry

Slide 80

Slide 80 text

The Axiom of Symmetry Let I = [0, 1], and let Iω denote the set of countable subsets of [0, 1].

Slide 81

Slide 81 text

The Axiom of Symmetry Let I = [0, 1], and let Iω denote the set of countable subsets of [0, 1]. AS: For every f : I → Iω, there are x, y ∈ I such that x ∈ f (y) and y ∈ f (x).

Slide 82

Slide 82 text

The Axiom of Symmetry Let I = [0, 1], and let Iω denote the set of countable subsets of [0, 1]. AS: For every f : I → Iω, there are x, y ∈ I such that x ∈ f (y) and y ∈ f (x). Lemma If CH is true, then AS is false.

Slide 83

Slide 83 text

The Axiom of Symmetry Let I = [0, 1], and let Iω denote the set of countable subsets of [0, 1]. AS: For every f : I → Iω, there are x, y ∈ I such that x ∈ f (y) and y ∈ f (x). Lemma If CH is true, then AS is false. Proof. Suppose CH is true and fix an enumeration of I: xα | α < ω1 .

Slide 84

Slide 84 text

The Axiom of Symmetry Let I = [0, 1], and let Iω denote the set of countable subsets of [0, 1]. AS: For every f : I → Iω, there are x, y ∈ I such that x ∈ f (y) and y ∈ f (x). Lemma If CH is true, then AS is false. Proof. Suppose CH is true and fix an enumeration of I: xα | α < ω1 . Define f : I → Iω by f (xα) = {xβ | β < α}.

Slide 85

Slide 85 text

The Axiom of Symmetry Let I = [0, 1], and let Iω denote the set of countable subsets of [0, 1]. AS: For every f : I → Iω, there are x, y ∈ I such that x ∈ f (y) and y ∈ f (x). Lemma If CH is true, then AS is false. Proof. Suppose CH is true and fix an enumeration of I: xα | α < ω1 . Define f : I → Iω by f (xα) = {xβ | β < α}. Then, for any α < β < ω1, xα ∈ f (xβ), so f is a counterexample to AS.

Slide 86

Slide 86 text

The Axiom of Symmetry AS is actually equivalent to the negation of CH and was introduced by Chris Freiling as an argument against CH.

Slide 87

Slide 87 text

The Axiom of Symmetry AS is actually equivalent to the negation of CH and was introduced by Chris Freiling as an argument against CH. Freiling’s Dartboard Argument:

Slide 88

Slide 88 text

The Axiom of Symmetry AS is actually equivalent to the negation of CH and was introduced by Chris Freiling as an argument against CH. Freiling’s Dartboard Argument: Fix an f : I → Iω.

Slide 89

Slide 89 text

The Axiom of Symmetry AS is actually equivalent to the negation of CH and was introduced by Chris Freiling as an argument against CH. Freiling’s Dartboard Argument: Fix an f : I → Iω. Throw two darts at the interval [0, 1].

Slide 90

Slide 90 text

The Axiom of Symmetry AS is actually equivalent to the negation of CH and was introduced by Chris Freiling as an argument against CH. Freiling’s Dartboard Argument: Fix an f : I → Iω. Throw two darts at the interval [0, 1]. If the first dart is thrown and lands at point x, then, since f (x) is countable and thus has measure 0, the probability that the second dart lands in f (x) is 0.

Slide 91

Slide 91 text

The Axiom of Symmetry AS is actually equivalent to the negation of CH and was introduced by Chris Freiling as an argument against CH. Freiling’s Dartboard Argument: Fix an f : I → Iω. Throw two darts at the interval [0, 1]. If the first dart is thrown and lands at point x, then, since f (x) is countable and thus has measure 0, the probability that the second dart lands in f (x) is 0. Since this is true no matter where the first dart lands, it should be true even before the first dart is thrown.

Slide 92

Slide 92 text

The Axiom of Symmetry AS is actually equivalent to the negation of CH and was introduced by Chris Freiling as an argument against CH. Freiling’s Dartboard Argument: Fix an f : I → Iω. Throw two darts at the interval [0, 1]. If the first dart is thrown and lands at point x, then, since f (x) is countable and thus has measure 0, the probability that the second dart lands in f (x) is 0. Since this is true no matter where the first dart lands, it should be true even before the first dart is thrown. By symmetry of the order in which the darts are thrown, if y denotes the point where the second dart lands, the probability that the first dart lands in f (y) is 0.

Slide 93

Slide 93 text

The Axiom of Symmetry AS is actually equivalent to the negation of CH and was introduced by Chris Freiling as an argument against CH. Freiling’s Dartboard Argument: Fix an f : I → Iω. Throw two darts at the interval [0, 1]. If the first dart is thrown and lands at point x, then, since f (x) is countable and thus has measure 0, the probability that the second dart lands in f (x) is 0. Since this is true no matter where the first dart lands, it should be true even before the first dart is thrown. By symmetry of the order in which the darts are thrown, if y denotes the point where the second dart lands, the probability that the first dart lands in f (y) is 0. So, almost surely, the two darts will land at two points witnessing that AS holds for f .

Slide 94

Slide 94 text

Problems with Freiling’s Arguments Two main objections can be raised.

Slide 95

Slide 95 text

Problems with Freiling’s Arguments Two main objections can be raised. One objection involves Lebesgue measurability:

Slide 96

Slide 96 text

Problems with Freiling’s Arguments Two main objections can be raised. One objection involves Lebesgue measurability: Freiling’s argument seems to appeal to an intuition that {(x, y) | x ∈ f (y)} and {(x, y) | y ∈ f (x)} both have measure 0.

Slide 97

Slide 97 text

Problems with Freiling’s Arguments Two main objections can be raised. One objection involves Lebesgue measurability: Freiling’s argument seems to appeal to an intuition that {(x, y) | x ∈ f (y)} and {(x, y) | y ∈ f (x)} both have measure 0. This intuition seems to require that there is a very well-behaved measure on the reals, which is precluded by the Axiom of Choice.

Slide 98

Slide 98 text

Problems with Freiling’s Arguments Two main objections can be raised. One objection involves Lebesgue measurability: Freiling’s argument seems to appeal to an intuition that {(x, y) | x ∈ f (y)} and {(x, y) | y ∈ f (x)} both have measure 0. This intuition seems to require that there is a very well-behaved measure on the reals, which is precluded by the Axiom of Choice. In fact, if f is a counterexample to AS, then both {(x, y) | x ∈ f (y)} and {(x, y) | y ∈ f (x)} are non-measurable.

Slide 99

Slide 99 text

Problems with Freiling’s Arguments Two main objections can be raised. One objection involves Lebesgue measurability: Freiling’s argument seems to appeal to an intuition that {(x, y) | x ∈ f (y)} and {(x, y) | y ∈ f (x)} both have measure 0. This intuition seems to require that there is a very well-behaved measure on the reals, which is precluded by the Axiom of Choice. In fact, if f is a counterexample to AS, then both {(x, y) | x ∈ f (y)} and {(x, y) | y ∈ f (x)} are non-measurable. The other objection to Freiling’s argument also features the Axiom of Choice in a prominent role.

Slide 100

Slide 100 text

Problems with Freiling’s Arguments Two main objections can be raised. One objection involves Lebesgue measurability: Freiling’s argument seems to appeal to an intuition that {(x, y) | x ∈ f (y)} and {(x, y) | y ∈ f (x)} both have measure 0. This intuition seems to require that there is a very well-behaved measure on the reals, which is precluded by the Axiom of Choice. In fact, if f is a counterexample to AS, then both {(x, y) | x ∈ f (y)} and {(x, y) | y ∈ f (x)} are non-measurable. The other objection to Freiling’s argument also features the Axiom of Choice in a prominent role. These two objections suggest that AS might really be more about Choice than about CH.

Slide 101

Slide 101 text

Solovay’s Model Soon after Cohen introduced it, Solovay used the technique of forcing to construct a model S of ZF + DC in which:

Slide 102

Slide 102 text

Solovay’s Model Soon after Cohen introduced it, Solovay used the technique of forcing to construct a model S of ZF + DC in which: 1 All sets of real numbers are Lebesgue measurable.

Slide 103

Slide 103 text

Solovay’s Model Soon after Cohen introduced it, Solovay used the technique of forcing to construct a model S of ZF + DC in which: 1 All sets of real numbers are Lebesgue measurable. 2 All sets of real numbers have the perfect set property.

Slide 104

Slide 104 text

Solovay’s Model Soon after Cohen introduced it, Solovay used the technique of forcing to construct a model S of ZF + DC in which: 1 All sets of real numbers are Lebesgue measurable. 2 All sets of real numbers have the perfect set property. The existence of an injective function f : ω1 → R is enough to construct a non-measurable set, so, in S, ℵ1 and 2ℵ0 are not even comparable.

Slide 105

Slide 105 text

Solovay’s Model Soon after Cohen introduced it, Solovay used the technique of forcing to construct a model S of ZF + DC in which: 1 All sets of real numbers are Lebesgue measurable. 2 All sets of real numbers have the perfect set property. The existence of an injective function f : ω1 → R is enough to construct a non-measurable set, so, in S, ℵ1 and 2ℵ0 are not even comparable. However, 2 implies that, in S, every set of real numbers is either countable or of cardinality 2ℵ0 , so a form of CH is true in S.

Slide 106

Slide 106 text

Solovay’s Model Soon after Cohen introduced it, Solovay used the technique of forcing to construct a model S of ZF + DC in which: 1 All sets of real numbers are Lebesgue measurable. 2 All sets of real numbers have the perfect set property. The existence of an injective function f : ω1 → R is enough to construct a non-measurable set, so, in S, ℵ1 and 2ℵ0 are not even comparable. However, 2 implies that, in S, every set of real numbers is either countable or of cardinality 2ℵ0 , so a form of CH is true in S. 1 implies that AS is true in S.

Slide 107

Slide 107 text

Closing Remarks