Slide 1

Slide 1 text

Simultaneously vanishing higher derived limits (Joint work with Jeffrey Bergfalk) Chris Lambie-Hanson Department of Mathematics and Applied Mathematics Virginia Commonwealth University Oaxaca 8 August 2019

Slide 2

Slide 2 text

I. Homological beginnings

Slide 3

Slide 3 text

Additivity Definition A homology theory is additive on a class of topological spaces C if, for every natural number p and every family {Xi | i ∈ J} such that each Xi and J Xi are in C, we have J Hp(Xi ) ∼ = Hp( J Xi ) via the map induced by the inclusions Xi → J Xi .

Slide 4

Slide 4 text

Additivity of strong homology Let Xn denote the n-dimensional Hawaiian earring, i.e., the one-point compactification of an infinite countable sum of copies of the n-dimensional open unit ball. Let ¯ Hp(X) denote the pth strong homology group of X.

Slide 5

Slide 5 text

Additivity of strong homology Let Xn denote the n-dimensional Hawaiian earring, i.e., the one-point compactification of an infinite countable sum of copies of the n-dimensional open unit ball. Let ¯ Hp(X) denote the pth strong homology group of X. Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov, ‘88) Suppose that 0 < p < n are natural numbers. Then N ¯ Hp(Xn) = ¯ Hp( N Xn) if and only if limn−p A = 0.

Slide 6

Slide 6 text

Additivity of strong homology Let Xn denote the n-dimensional Hawaiian earring, i.e., the one-point compactification of an infinite countable sum of copies of the n-dimensional open unit ball. Let ¯ Hp(X) denote the pth strong homology group of X. Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov, ‘88) Suppose that 0 < p < n are natural numbers. Then N ¯ Hp(Xn) = ¯ Hp( N Xn) if and only if limn−p A = 0. Consequently, if strong homology is additive on closed subsets of Euclidean space, then limn A = 0 for all n ≥ 1.

Slide 7

Slide 7 text

A Hawaiian earring

Slide 8

Slide 8 text

Compact supports Definition A homology theory has compact supports on a class of topological spaces C if, for every natural number p and every space X in C, Hp(X) is isomorphic to the direct limit of Hp(K) for compact subspaces K of X via the map induced by the inclusion maps K → X.

Slide 9

Slide 9 text

Compact supports Definition A homology theory has compact supports on a class of topological spaces C if, for every natural number p and every space X in C, Hp(X) is isomorphic to the direct limit of Hp(K) for compact subspaces K of X via the map induced by the inclusion maps K → X. Mardeˇ si´ c and Prasolov also showed that if strong homology has countable supports on closed subsets of Euclidean space, then limn A = 0 for all n ≥ 1.

Slide 10

Slide 10 text

The inverse system A Given a function f ∈ ωω, let I(f ) = {(k, m) ∈ ω × ω | m ≤ f (k)} , and let Af = I(f ) Z.

Slide 11

Slide 11 text

The inverse system A Given a function f ∈ ωω, let I(f ) = {(k, m) ∈ ω × ω | m ≤ f (k)} , and let Af = I(f ) Z. If f ≤ g, we have a projection map pfg : Ag → Af .

Slide 12

Slide 12 text

The inverse system A Given a function f ∈ ωω, let I(f ) = {(k, m) ∈ ω × ω | m ≤ f (k)} , and let Af = I(f ) Z. If f ≤ g, we have a projection map pfg : Ag → Af . A is the inverse system Af , pfg f , g ∈ ωω, f ≤ g .

Slide 13

Slide 13 text

The inverse system A Given a function f ∈ ωω, let I(f ) = {(k, m) ∈ ω × ω | m ≤ f (k)} , and let Af = I(f ) Z. If f ≤ g, we have a projection map pfg : Ag → Af . A is the inverse system Af , pfg f , g ∈ ωω, f ≤ g . Its inverse limit, lim0 A, is ω ω Z.

Slide 14

Slide 14 text

Condensed mathematics The question of the consistency of limn A = 0 for n ≥ 1 arose independently in recent work of Clausen and Scholze on condensed mathematics, a new approach to doing algebra in situations in which the algebraic structures carry topologies.

Slide 15

Slide 15 text

Condensed mathematics The question of the consistency of limn A = 0 for n ≥ 1 arose independently in recent work of Clausen and Scholze on condensed mathematics, a new approach to doing algebra in situations in which the algebraic structures carry topologies. They introduced the category of condensed abelian groups as a replacement for topological abelian groups.

Slide 16

Slide 16 text

Condensed mathematics The question of the consistency of limn A = 0 for n ≥ 1 arose independently in recent work of Clausen and Scholze on condensed mathematics, a new approach to doing algebra in situations in which the algebraic structures carry topologies. They introduced the category of condensed abelian groups as a replacement for topological abelian groups. The natural question of whether pro-abelian groups embed fully faithfully into condensed abelian groups is equivalent, in its simplest case, to the question of whether limn A = 0 for n ≥ 1.

Slide 17

Slide 17 text

II. Set theoretic reformulations

Slide 18

Slide 18 text

Nontrivial coherent families Given f , g ∈ ωω, let f ∧ g denote their greatest lower bound in (ωω, ≤).

Slide 19

Slide 19 text

Nontrivial coherent families Given f , g ∈ ωω, let f ∧ g denote their greatest lower bound in (ωω, ≤). Definition Let Φ = {ϕf : I(f ) → Z | f ∈ ωω} be a family of functions.

Slide 20

Slide 20 text

Nontrivial coherent families Given f , g ∈ ωω, let f ∧ g denote their greatest lower bound in (ωω, ≤). Definition Let Φ = {ϕf : I(f ) → Z | f ∈ ωω} be a family of functions. 1 Φ is coherent if ϕf I(f ∧ g) =∗ ϕg I(f ∧ g) for all f , g ∈ ωω.

Slide 21

Slide 21 text

Nontrivial coherent families Given f , g ∈ ωω, let f ∧ g denote their greatest lower bound in (ωω, ≤). Definition Let Φ = {ϕf : I(f ) → Z | f ∈ ωω} be a family of functions. 1 Φ is coherent if ϕf I(f ∧ g) =∗ ϕg I(f ∧ g) for all f , g ∈ ωω. 2 Φ is trivial if there is a function ψ : ω × ω → Z such that ϕf =∗ ψ I(f ) for all f ∈ ωω.

Slide 22

Slide 22 text

Nontrivial coherent families Given f , g ∈ ωω, let f ∧ g denote their greatest lower bound in (ωω, ≤). Definition Let Φ = {ϕf : I(f ) → Z | f ∈ ωω} be a family of functions. 1 Φ is coherent if ϕf I(f ∧ g) =∗ ϕg I(f ∧ g) for all f , g ∈ ωω. 2 Φ is trivial if there is a function ψ : ω × ω → Z such that ϕf =∗ ψ I(f ) for all f ∈ ωω. Clearly, a trivial family is coherent.

Slide 23

Slide 23 text

Nontrivial coherent families Given f , g ∈ ωω, let f ∧ g denote their greatest lower bound in (ωω, ≤). Definition Let Φ = {ϕf : I(f ) → Z | f ∈ ωω} be a family of functions. 1 Φ is coherent if ϕf I(f ∧ g) =∗ ϕg I(f ∧ g) for all f , g ∈ ωω. 2 Φ is trivial if there is a function ψ : ω × ω → Z such that ϕf =∗ ψ I(f ) for all f ∈ ωω. Clearly, a trivial family is coherent. A nontrivial coherent family Φ is a clear example of set theoretic incompactness: each local family {ϕf | f < g} (for a fixed g ∈ ωω) is trivial, as witnessed by ϕg itself, but the entire family is not.

Slide 24

Slide 24 text

2-dimensional nontrivial coherence Definition Let Φ = ϕfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z f , g ∈ ωω .

Slide 25

Slide 25 text

2-dimensional nontrivial coherence Definition Let Φ = ϕfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z f , g ∈ ωω . 1 Φ is alternating if ϕfg = −ϕgf for all f , g ∈ ωω.

Slide 26

Slide 26 text

2-dimensional nontrivial coherence Definition Let Φ = ϕfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z f , g ∈ ωω . 1 Φ is alternating if ϕfg = −ϕgf for all f , g ∈ ωω. 2 Φ is 2-coherent if it is alternating and ϕfg + ϕgh =∗ ϕfh for all f , g, h ∈ ωω. (All functions restricted to I(f ∧ g ∧ h).)

Slide 27

Slide 27 text

2-dimensional nontrivial coherence Definition Let Φ = ϕfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z f , g ∈ ωω . 1 Φ is alternating if ϕfg = −ϕgf for all f , g ∈ ωω. 2 Φ is 2-coherent if it is alternating and ϕfg + ϕgh =∗ ϕfh for all f , g, h ∈ ωω. (All functions restricted to I(f ∧ g ∧ h).) 3 Φ is 2-trivial if there is a family Ψ = {ψf : I(f ) → Z | f ∈ ωω} such that ψg − ψf =∗ ϕfg for all f , g ∈ ωω.

Slide 28

Slide 28 text

2-dimensional nontrivial coherence Definition Let Φ = ϕfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z f , g ∈ ωω . 1 Φ is alternating if ϕfg = −ϕgf for all f , g ∈ ωω. 2 Φ is 2-coherent if it is alternating and ϕfg + ϕgh =∗ ϕfh for all f , g, h ∈ ωω. (All functions restricted to I(f ∧ g ∧ h).) 3 Φ is 2-trivial if there is a family Ψ = {ψf : I(f ) → Z | f ∈ ωω} such that ψg − ψf =∗ ϕfg for all f , g ∈ ωω. Again, a 2-trivial family is 2-coherent.

Slide 29

Slide 29 text

2-dimensional nontrivial coherence Definition Let Φ = ϕfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z f , g ∈ ωω . 1 Φ is alternating if ϕfg = −ϕgf for all f , g ∈ ωω. 2 Φ is 2-coherent if it is alternating and ϕfg + ϕgh =∗ ϕfh for all f , g, h ∈ ωω. (All functions restricted to I(f ∧ g ∧ h).) 3 Φ is 2-trivial if there is a family Ψ = {ψf : I(f ) → Z | f ∈ ωω} such that ψg − ψf =∗ ϕfg for all f , g ∈ ωω. Again, a 2-trivial family is 2-coherent. A non-2-trivial 2-coherent family Φ is an example of incompactness: each local family {ϕfg | f , g < h} (for a fixed h ∈ ωω) is 2-trivial, as witnessed by the family {−ϕfh | f < h}, but the entire family is not.

Slide 30

Slide 30 text

n-dimensional nontrivial coherence Given a sequence f = (f0, . . . , fn−1) and i < n, f i is the sequence of length n − 1 formed by removing fi from f . Definition Fix n ≥ 2, and let Φ = ϕ f : I(∧f ) → Z f ∈ (ωω)n .

Slide 31

Slide 31 text

n-dimensional nontrivial coherence Given a sequence f = (f0, . . . , fn−1) and i < n, f i is the sequence of length n − 1 formed by removing fi from f . Definition Fix n ≥ 2, and let Φ = ϕ f : I(∧f ) → Z f ∈ (ωω)n . 1 Φ is alternating if ϕ f = sgn(σ)ϕ σ(f ) for all f ∈ (ωω)n and all permutations σ.

Slide 32

Slide 32 text

n-dimensional nontrivial coherence Given a sequence f = (f0, . . . , fn−1) and i < n, f i is the sequence of length n − 1 formed by removing fi from f . Definition Fix n ≥ 2, and let Φ = ϕ f : I(∧f ) → Z f ∈ (ωω)n . 1 Φ is alternating if ϕ f = sgn(σ)ϕ σ(f ) for all f ∈ (ωω)n and all permutations σ. 2 Φ is n-coherent if it is alternating and n i=0 (−1)i ϕ f i =∗ 0 for all f ∈ (ωω)n+1.

Slide 33

Slide 33 text

n-dimensional nontrivial coherence Given a sequence f = (f0, . . . , fn−1) and i < n, f i is the sequence of length n − 1 formed by removing fi from f . Definition Fix n ≥ 2, and let Φ = ϕ f : I(∧f ) → Z f ∈ (ωω)n . 1 Φ is alternating if ϕ f = sgn(σ)ϕ σ(f ) for all f ∈ (ωω)n and all permutations σ. 2 Φ is n-coherent if it is alternating and n i=0 (−1)i ϕ f i =∗ 0 for all f ∈ (ωω)n+1. 3 Φ is n-trivial if there is an alternating family ψ f : I(∧f ) → Z f ∈ (ωω)n−1 such that n−1 i=0 (−1)i ψ f i =∗ ϕ f for all f ∈ (ωω)n.

Slide 34

Slide 34 text

limn A and nontrivial coherence Coherent and trivial can now be thought of as 1-coherent and 1-trivial.

Slide 35

Slide 35 text

limn A and nontrivial coherence Coherent and trivial can now be thought of as 1-coherent and 1-trivial. Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov (n = 1), Bergfalk (n ≥ 2)) Fix n ≥ 1. Then limn A = 0 if and only if every n-coherent family Φ = ϕ f f ∈ (ωω)n is n-trivial.

Slide 36

Slide 36 text

limn A and nontrivial coherence Coherent and trivial can now be thought of as 1-coherent and 1-trivial. Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov (n = 1), Bergfalk (n ≥ 2)) Fix n ≥ 1. Then limn A = 0 if and only if every n-coherent family Φ = ϕ f f ∈ (ωω)n is n-trivial. Thus, to prove that limn A = 0, it suffices to show that every n-coherent family is n-trivial.

Slide 37

Slide 37 text

lim1 A Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov, Simon, ’88) CH ⇒ lim1 A = 0.

Slide 38

Slide 38 text

lim1 A Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov, Simon, ’88) CH ⇒ lim1 A = 0. Theorem (Dow-Simon-Vaughan, ‘89) d = ℵ1 ⇒ lim1 A = 0.

Slide 39

Slide 39 text

lim1 A Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov, Simon, ’88) CH ⇒ lim1 A = 0. Theorem (Dow-Simon-Vaughan, ‘89) d = ℵ1 ⇒ lim1 A = 0. PFA ⇒ lim1 A = 0.

Slide 40

Slide 40 text

lim1 A Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov, Simon, ’88) CH ⇒ lim1 A = 0. Theorem (Dow-Simon-Vaughan, ‘89) d = ℵ1 ⇒ lim1 A = 0. PFA ⇒ lim1 A = 0. Theorem (Todorcevic, ‘98) OCA ⇒ lim1 A = 0.

Slide 41

Slide 41 text

lim1 A Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov, Simon, ’88) CH ⇒ lim1 A = 0. Theorem (Dow-Simon-Vaughan, ‘89) d = ℵ1 ⇒ lim1 A = 0. PFA ⇒ lim1 A = 0. Theorem (Todorcevic, ‘98) OCA ⇒ lim1 A = 0. MAℵ1 ⇒ lim1 A = 0.

Slide 42

Slide 42 text

lim1 A Theorem (Mardeˇ si´ c-Prasolov, Simon, ’88) CH ⇒ lim1 A = 0. Theorem (Dow-Simon-Vaughan, ‘89) d = ℵ1 ⇒ lim1 A = 0. PFA ⇒ lim1 A = 0. Theorem (Todorcevic, ‘98) OCA ⇒ lim1 A = 0. MAℵ1 ⇒ lim1 A = 0. Theorem (Kamo, ‘93) V Add(ω,ω2) |= “ lim1 A = 0”.

Slide 43

Slide 43 text

Higher limits Theorem (Bergfalk, ‘17) PFA ⇒ lim2 A = 0.

Slide 44

Slide 44 text

Higher limits Theorem (Bergfalk, ‘17) PFA ⇒ lim2 A = 0. Theorem (Bergfalk-LH, ‘19) Suppose that κ is a measurable cardinal and that P is a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings. Then V P |= “ lim nA = 0 for all n ≥ 1”.

Slide 45

Slide 45 text

III. A strong ∆-system lemma

Slide 46

Slide 46 text

Hechler forcing Recall that conditions of Hechler forcing are of the form p = (sp, f p), where sp ∈ <ωω and f p ∈ ωω.

Slide 47

Slide 47 text

Hechler forcing Recall that conditions of Hechler forcing are of the form p = (sp, f p), where sp ∈ <ωω and f p ∈ ωω. If p and q are Hechler conditions, then q ≤ p if and only if • sq end-extends sp; • f q ≥ f p; • sq(k) > f p(k) for all k ∈ dom(sq) \ dom(qp).

Slide 48

Slide 48 text

Hechler forcing Recall that conditions of Hechler forcing are of the form p = (sp, f p), where sp ∈ <ωω and f p ∈ ωω. If p and q are Hechler conditions, then q ≤ p if and only if • sq end-extends sp; • f q ≥ f p; • sq(k) > f p(k) for all k ∈ dom(sq) \ dom(qp). In what follows, P denotes a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings, where κ is a fixed regular uncountable cardinal.

Slide 49

Slide 49 text

Hechler forcing Recall that conditions of Hechler forcing are of the form p = (sp, f p), where sp ∈ <ωω and f p ∈ ωω. If p and q are Hechler conditions, then q ≤ p if and only if • sq end-extends sp; • f q ≥ f p; • sq(k) > f p(k) for all k ∈ dom(sq) \ dom(qp). In what follows, P denotes a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings, where κ is a fixed regular uncountable cardinal. As a result of a simple ∆-system argument, we know that, if pα | α < κ is a sequence of conditions in P, then there is an unbounded set A ⊆ κ such that pα | α ∈ A consists of pairwise compatible conditions.

Slide 50

Slide 50 text

A first attempt In our proof, we will be working with families of conditions indexed by finite increasing sequences from κ. We would like to use a multi-dimensional ∆-system argument to perform a similar sort of uniformization. A na¨ ıve first attempt might be:

Slide 51

Slide 51 text

A first attempt In our proof, we will be working with families of conditions indexed by finite increasing sequences from κ. We would like to use a multi-dimensional ∆-system argument to perform a similar sort of uniformization. A na¨ ıve first attempt might be: Lemma? Suppose that κ is sufficiently large (e.g., measurable) and fix n ≥ 1. Given any family pα | α ∈ [κ]n from P, there is an unbounded A ⊆ κ such that pα | α ∈ [A]n consists of pairwise compatible conditions.

Slide 52

Slide 52 text

A first attempt In our proof, we will be working with families of conditions indexed by finite increasing sequences from κ. We would like to use a multi-dimensional ∆-system argument to perform a similar sort of uniformization. A na¨ ıve first attempt might be: Lemma? Suppose that κ is sufficiently large (e.g., measurable) and fix n ≥ 1. Given any family pα | α ∈ [κ]n from P, there is an unbounded A ⊆ κ such that pα | α ∈ [A]n consists of pairwise compatible conditions. This is obviously false. If n = 2, for example, we can define pαβ | α < β < κ such that pαβ(α) is (a name for) ( 0 , 0) and pαβ(β) is ( 1 , 0). Then, for any α < β < γ, we have pαβ ⊥ pβγ.

Slide 53

Slide 53 text

A first attempt In our proof, we will be working with families of conditions indexed by finite increasing sequences from κ. We would like to use a multi-dimensional ∆-system argument to perform a similar sort of uniformization. A na¨ ıve first attempt might be: Lemma? Suppose that κ is sufficiently large (e.g., measurable) and fix n ≥ 1. Given any family pα | α ∈ [κ]n from P, there is an unbounded A ⊆ κ such that pα | α ∈ [A]n consists of pairwise compatible conditions. This is obviously false. If n = 2, for example, we can define pαβ | α < β < κ such that pαβ(α) is (a name for) ( 0 , 0) and pαβ(β) is ( 1 , 0). Then, for any α < β < γ, we have pαβ ⊥ pβγ. This turns out to be the only obstacle, though.

Slide 54

Slide 54 text

Aligned sets Definition Fix n ≥ 1 and suppose that α = α0, . . . , αn−1 and β = β0, . . . , βn−1 are in [κ]n (and hence are increasing). We say that α and β are aligned if, for all i, j < n, αi = βj ⇒ i = j.

Slide 55

Slide 55 text

Aligned sets Definition Fix n ≥ 1 and suppose that α = α0, . . . , αn−1 and β = β0, . . . , βn−1 are in [κ]n (and hence are increasing). We say that α and β are aligned if, for all i, j < n, αi = βj ⇒ i = j. Lemma Suppose that κ is weakly compact, and fix n ≥ 1. Given any family pα | α ∈ [κ]n , there is an unbounded A ⊆ κ such that, for all α, β ∈ [κ]n, if α and β are aligned, then pα and p β are compatible.

Slide 56

Slide 56 text

Aligned sets Definition Fix n ≥ 1 and suppose that α = α0, . . . , αn−1 and β = β0, . . . , βn−1 are in [κ]n (and hence are increasing). We say that α and β are aligned if, for all i, j < n, αi = βj ⇒ i = j. Lemma Suppose that κ is weakly compact, and fix n ≥ 1. Given any family pα | α ∈ [κ]n , there is an unbounded A ⊆ κ such that, for all α, β ∈ [κ]n, if α and β are aligned, then pα and p β are compatible. We actually require a bit more than this, for which we seem to need a measurable cardinal.

Slide 57

Slide 57 text

The ∆-system lemma Lemma Suppose that κ is measurable, with normal measure U, and fix n ≥ 1. Let P be a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings, and let {pα | α ∈ [κ]n} be a family of conditions in P.

Slide 58

Slide 58 text

The ∆-system lemma Lemma Suppose that κ is measurable, with normal measure U, and fix n ≥ 1. Let P be a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings, and let {pα | α ∈ [κ]n} be a family of conditions in P. Then there is a set A ∈ U and conditions {pα | α ∈ [A]

Slide 59

Slide 59 text

The ∆-system lemma Lemma Suppose that κ is measurable, with normal measure U, and fix n ≥ 1. Let P be a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings, and let {pα | α ∈ [κ]n} be a family of conditions in P. Then there is a set A ∈ U and conditions {pα | α ∈ [A]

Slide 60

Slide 60 text

The ∆-system lemma Lemma Suppose that κ is measurable, with normal measure U, and fix n ≥ 1. Let P be a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings, and let {pα | α ∈ [κ]n} be a family of conditions in P. Then there is a set A ∈ U and conditions {pα | α ∈ [A]

Slide 61

Slide 61 text

The ∆-system lemma Lemma Suppose that κ is measurable, with normal measure U, and fix n ≥ 1. Let P be a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings, and let {pα | α ∈ [κ]n} be a family of conditions in P. Then there is a set A ∈ U and conditions {pα | α ∈ [A]

Slide 62

Slide 62 text

IV. Vanishing higher limits

Slide 63

Slide 63 text

Proof sketch (n = 2) Main Theorem Suppose that κ is a measurable cardinal and that P is a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings. In V P, for every n ≥ 1, every n-coherent family ϕ f f ∈ (ωω)n is n-trivial.

Slide 64

Slide 64 text

Proof sketch (n = 2) Main Theorem Suppose that κ is a measurable cardinal and that P is a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings. In V P, for every n ≥ 1, every n-coherent family ϕ f f ∈ (ωω)n is n-trivial. Proof sketch for n = 2: We start by making some simplifying assumptions.

Slide 65

Slide 65 text

Proof sketch (n = 2) Main Theorem Suppose that κ is a measurable cardinal and that P is a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings. In V P, for every n ≥ 1, every n-coherent family ϕ f f ∈ (ωω)n is n-trivial. Proof sketch for n = 2: We start by making some simplifying assumptions. • To show that a 2-coherent family of functions is trivial, it suffices to find a trivialization indexed by some ≤∗-cofinal family of functions.

Slide 66

Slide 66 text

Proof sketch (n = 2) Main Theorem Suppose that κ is a measurable cardinal and that P is a length-κ finite support iteration of Hechler forcings. In V P, for every n ≥ 1, every n-coherent family ϕ f f ∈ (ωω)n is n-trivial. Proof sketch for n = 2: We start by making some simplifying assumptions. • To show that a 2-coherent family of functions is trivial, it suffices to find a trivialization indexed by some ≤∗-cofinal family of functions. • Since the Hechler reals fα | α < κ are ≤∗-increasing and cofinal, it suffices to find a trivialization indexed by fα | α ∈ B for some cofinal B ⊆ κ.

Slide 67

Slide 67 text

• The 2-triviality of a 2-coherent family ϕfg f , g ∈ ωω is equivalent to the following statement:

Slide 68

Slide 68 text

• The 2-triviality of a 2-coherent family ϕfg f , g ∈ ωω is equivalent to the following statement: There is an alternating family ψfg f , g ∈ ωω such that each ψfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z is finitely supported and, for all f , g, h ∈ ωω, (ϕgh − ψgh) − (ϕfh − ψfh) + (ϕfg − ψfg) = 0.

Slide 69

Slide 69 text

• The 2-triviality of a 2-coherent family ϕfg f , g ∈ ωω is equivalent to the following statement: There is an alternating family ψfg f , g ∈ ωω such that each ψfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z is finitely supported and, for all f , g, h ∈ ωω, (ϕgh − ψgh) − (ϕfh − ψfh) + (ϕfg − ψfg) = 0. In V , fix a condition p ∈ P and a P-name ˙ Φ = ˙ ϕαβ α, β < κ for a 2-coherent family indexed by pairs of Hechler reals.

Slide 70

Slide 70 text

• The 2-triviality of a 2-coherent family ϕfg f , g ∈ ωω is equivalent to the following statement: There is an alternating family ψfg f , g ∈ ωω such that each ψfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z is finitely supported and, for all f , g, h ∈ ωω, (ϕgh − ψgh) − (ϕfh − ψfh) + (ϕfg − ψfg) = 0. In V , fix a condition p ∈ P and a P-name ˙ Φ = ˙ ϕαβ α, β < κ for a 2-coherent family indexed by pairs of Hechler reals. For α < β < γ < κ above the domain of p, let ˙ e(α, β, γ) be a P name for ϕβγ − ϕαγ + ϕαβ, let ˙ ¯ e(α, β, γ) be a P-name for its restriction to its (finite) support, and fix pαβγ ≤ p such that

Slide 71

Slide 71 text

• The 2-triviality of a 2-coherent family ϕfg f , g ∈ ωω is equivalent to the following statement: There is an alternating family ψfg f , g ∈ ωω such that each ψfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z is finitely supported and, for all f , g, h ∈ ωω, (ϕgh − ψgh) − (ϕfh − ψfh) + (ϕfg − ψfg) = 0. In V , fix a condition p ∈ P and a P-name ˙ Φ = ˙ ϕαβ α, β < κ for a 2-coherent family indexed by pairs of Hechler reals. For α < β < γ < κ above the domain of p, let ˙ e(α, β, γ) be a P name for ϕβγ − ϕαγ + ϕαβ, let ˙ ¯ e(α, β, γ) be a P-name for its restriction to its (finite) support, and fix pαβγ ≤ p such that • pαβγ fα ≤ fβ ≤ fγ;

Slide 72

Slide 72 text

• The 2-triviality of a 2-coherent family ϕfg f , g ∈ ωω is equivalent to the following statement: There is an alternating family ψfg f , g ∈ ωω such that each ψfg : I(f ∧ g) → Z is finitely supported and, for all f , g, h ∈ ωω, (ϕgh − ψgh) − (ϕfh − ψfh) + (ϕfg − ψfg) = 0. In V , fix a condition p ∈ P and a P-name ˙ Φ = ˙ ϕαβ α, β < κ for a 2-coherent family indexed by pairs of Hechler reals. For α < β < γ < κ above the domain of p, let ˙ e(α, β, γ) be a P name for ϕβγ − ϕαγ + ϕαβ, let ˙ ¯ e(α, β, γ) be a P-name for its restriction to its (finite) support, and fix pαβγ ≤ p such that • pαβγ fα ≤ fβ ≤ fγ; • pαβγ decides the value of ˙ ¯ e(α, β, γ).

Slide 73

Slide 73 text

Apply our ∆-system lemma to obtain A ∈ U and conditions {pα | α ∈ [A]<3} such that

Slide 74

Slide 74 text

Apply our ∆-system lemma to obtain A ∈ U and conditions {pα | α ∈ [A]<3} such that • for all α β in [A]≤3, we have dom(pα ) dom(p β ) and pα = p β dom(pα );

Slide 75

Slide 75 text

Apply our ∆-system lemma to obtain A ∈ U and conditions {pα | α ∈ [A]<3} such that • for all α β in [A]≤3, we have dom(pα ) dom(p β ) and pα = p β dom(pα ); • for all α ∈ [A]

Slide 76

Slide 76 text

Apply our ∆-system lemma to obtain A ∈ U and conditions {pα | α ∈ [A]<3} such that • for all α β in [A]≤3, we have dom(pα ) dom(p β ) and pα = p β dom(pα ); • for all α ∈ [A]

Slide 77

Slide 77 text

Apply our ∆-system lemma to obtain A ∈ U and conditions {pα | α ∈ [A]<3} such that • for all α β in [A]≤3, we have dom(pα ) dom(p β ) and pα = p β dom(pα ); • for all α ∈ [A]

Slide 78

Slide 78 text

We claim that p∅ forces ˙ Φ to be trivial.

Slide 79

Slide 79 text

We claim that p∅ forces ˙ Φ to be trivial. In V , partition A into unbounded sets Γ0, Γ1, Γ2.

Slide 80

Slide 80 text

We claim that p∅ forces ˙ Φ to be trivial. In V , partition A into unbounded sets Γ0, Γ1, Γ2. Let G be P-generic with p∅ ∈ G. The following facts, which hold in V [G], are the point of our ∆-system lemma:

Slide 81

Slide 81 text

We claim that p∅ forces ˙ Φ to be trivial. In V , partition A into unbounded sets Γ0, Γ1, Γ2. Let G be P-generic with p∅ ∈ G. The following facts, which hold in V [G], are the point of our ∆-system lemma: • B := {α ∈ Γ0 | pα ∈ G} is unbounded.

Slide 82

Slide 82 text

We claim that p∅ forces ˙ Φ to be trivial. In V , partition A into unbounded sets Γ0, Γ1, Γ2. Let G be P-generic with p∅ ∈ G. The following facts, which hold in V [G], are the point of our ∆-system lemma: • B := {α ∈ Γ0 | pα ∈ G} is unbounded. • For all α < β in B, there is αβ ∈ Γ1 \ β such that pα αβ , pβ αβ ∈ G.

Slide 83

Slide 83 text

We claim that p∅ forces ˙ Φ to be trivial. In V , partition A into unbounded sets Γ0, Γ1, Γ2. Let G be P-generic with p∅ ∈ G. The following facts, which hold in V [G], are the point of our ∆-system lemma: • B := {α ∈ Γ0 | pα ∈ G} is unbounded. • For all α < β in B, there is αβ ∈ Γ1 \ β such that pα αβ , pβ αβ ∈ G. • For all α < β < γ in B, there is αβγ ∈ Γ2 \ max{ αβ, αγ, βγ} such that pα αβ αβγ , pα αγ αβγ , pβ αβ αβγ , pβ βγ αβγ , pγ αγ, αβγ , pγ βγ, αβγ ∈ G.

Slide 84

Slide 84 text

For α < β in B, let ψαβ := e(α, β, αβ) = ϕβ αβ − ϕα αβ + ϕαβ.

Slide 85

Slide 85 text

For α < β in B, let ψαβ := e(α, β, αβ) = ϕβ αβ − ϕα αβ + ϕαβ. We claim that this works. To see this, fix α < β < γ in B. We must show that e(α, β, γ) = ψβγ − ψαγ + ψαβ.

Slide 86

Slide 86 text

For α < β in B, let ψαβ := e(α, β, αβ) = ϕβ αβ − ϕα αβ + ϕαβ. We claim that this works. To see this, fix α < β < γ in B. We must show that e(α, β, γ) = ψβγ − ψαγ + ψαβ. NOTE: For any α < β < γ < δ < κ, we have e(β, γ, δ) − e(α, γ, δ) + e(α, β, δ) − e(α, β, γ) = 0.

Slide 87

Slide 87 text

For α < β in B, let ψαβ := e(α, β, αβ) = ϕβ αβ − ϕα αβ + ϕαβ. We claim that this works. To see this, fix α < β < γ in B. We must show that e(α, β, γ) = ψβγ − ψαγ + ψαβ. NOTE: For any α < β < γ < δ < κ, we have e(β, γ, δ) − e(α, γ, δ) + e(α, β, δ) − e(α, β, γ) = 0. Thus, e(α, β, γ) = e(β, γ, αβγ) − e(α, γ, αβγ) + e(α, β, αβγ).

Slide 88

Slide 88 text

For α < β in B, let ψαβ := e(α, β, αβ) = ϕβ αβ − ϕα αβ + ϕαβ. We claim that this works. To see this, fix α < β < γ in B. We must show that e(α, β, γ) = ψβγ − ψαγ + ψαβ. NOTE: For any α < β < γ < δ < κ, we have e(β, γ, δ) − e(α, γ, δ) + e(α, β, δ) − e(α, β, γ) = 0. Thus, e(α, β, γ) = e(β, γ, αβγ) − e(α, γ, αβγ) + e(α, β, αβγ). e(β, γ, αβγ) = −e(γ, βγ, αβγ) + e(β, βγ, αβγ) + e(β, γ, βγ) = −e + e + ψβγ = ψβγ

Slide 89

Slide 89 text

For α < β in B, let ψαβ := e(α, β, αβ) = ϕβ αβ − ϕα αβ + ϕαβ. We claim that this works. To see this, fix α < β < γ in B. We must show that e(α, β, γ) = ψβγ − ψαγ + ψαβ. NOTE: For any α < β < γ < δ < κ, we have e(β, γ, δ) − e(α, γ, δ) + e(α, β, δ) − e(α, β, γ) = 0. Thus, e(α, β, γ) = e(β, γ, αβγ) − e(α, γ, αβγ) + e(α, β, αβγ). e(β, γ, αβγ) = −e(γ, βγ, αβγ) + e(β, βγ, αβγ) + e(β, γ, βγ) = −e + e + ψβγ = ψβγ Similarly for e(α, γ, αβγ) and e(α, β, αβγ).

Slide 90

Slide 90 text

For α < β in B, let ψαβ := e(α, β, αβ) = ϕβ αβ − ϕα αβ + ϕαβ. We claim that this works. To see this, fix α < β < γ in B. We must show that e(α, β, γ) = ψβγ − ψαγ + ψαβ. NOTE: For any α < β < γ < δ < κ, we have e(β, γ, δ) − e(α, γ, δ) + e(α, β, δ) − e(α, β, γ) = 0. Thus, e(α, β, γ) = e(β, γ, αβγ) − e(α, γ, αβγ) + e(α, β, αβγ). e(β, γ, αβγ) = −e(γ, βγ, αβγ) + e(β, βγ, αβγ) + e(β, γ, βγ) = −e + e + ψβγ = ψβγ Similarly for e(α, γ, αβγ) and e(α, β, αβγ). This reduces to e(α, β, γ) = ψβγ − ψαγ + ψαβ, as desired.

Slide 91

Slide 91 text

V. Further directions

Slide 92

Slide 92 text

Optimality There are a number of questions one can ask about the optimality of our theorem.

Slide 93

Slide 93 text

Optimality There are a number of questions one can ask about the optimality of our theorem. Question What is the consistency strength of the statement “ limn A = 0 for all n ≥ 1”?

Slide 94

Slide 94 text

Optimality There are a number of questions one can ask about the optimality of our theorem. Question What is the consistency strength of the statement “ limn A = 0 for all n ≥ 1”? Question How small can the continuum be in a model of “ limn A = 0 for all n ≥ 1”?

Slide 95

Slide 95 text

Optimality There are a number of questions one can ask about the optimality of our theorem. Question What is the consistency strength of the statement “ limn A = 0 for all n ≥ 1”? Question How small can the continuum be in a model of “ limn A = 0 for all n ≥ 1”? We conjecture that it must be greater than ℵω. A natural place to look is the model obtained from adding ℵω+1 Cohen reals to a model of CH.

Slide 96

Slide 96 text

Strong homology Question Is it consistent that strong homology is additive on some nice class of topological spaces, e.g., locally compact metric spaces?

Slide 97

Slide 97 text

Strong homology Question Is it consistent that strong homology is additive on some nice class of topological spaces, e.g., locally compact metric spaces? Question Is it consistent that strong homology has compact supports on some nice class of topological spaces, e.g., locally compact metric spaces?

Slide 98

Slide 98 text

Strong homology Question Is it consistent that strong homology is additive on some nice class of topological spaces, e.g., locally compact metric spaces? Question Is it consistent that strong homology has compact supports on some nice class of topological spaces, e.g., locally compact metric spaces? The model for our Main Theorem is a natural first place to look for these questions.

Slide 99

Slide 99 text

Results contained in “Simultaneously vanishing higher derived limits,” joint with Jeffrey Bergfalk. Available at: https://arxiv.org/abs/1907.11744 All artwork by Josef Albers, inspired by visits to Monte Alban

Slide 100

Slide 100 text

Thank you!