Slide 1

Slide 1 text

Pseudo-Prikry Sequences Chris Lambie-Hanson Department of Mathematics and Applied Mathematics Virginia Commonwealth University Prikry Forcing Online 14 December 2020

Slide 2

Slide 2 text

I. A brief history

Slide 3

Slide 3 text

The basic premise

Slide 4

Slide 4 text

The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors.

Slide 5

Slide 5 text

The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors. In the last 30 years, some results have given some indication about why this might be the case.

Slide 6

Slide 6 text

The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors. In the last 30 years, some results have given some indication about why this might be the case. These results all have the following flavor:

Slide 7

Slide 7 text

The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors. In the last 30 years, some results have given some indication about why this might be the case. These results all have the following flavor: If V is an inner model of W and there is a regular cardinal in V that is singular in W (and certain other cardinals are preserved from V to W ), then there is an object in W that resembles a generic object over V for some Prikry- type forcing.

Slide 8

Slide 8 text

The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors. In the last 30 years, some results have given some indication about why this might be the case. These results all have the following flavor: If V is an inner model of W and there is a regular cardinal in V that is singular in W (and certain other cardinals are preserved from V to W ), then there is an object in W that resembles a generic object over V for some Prikry- type forcing. We call such objects pseudo-Prikry sequences.

Slide 9

Slide 9 text

Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters).

Slide 10

Slide 10 text

Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters). For example, if U is a normal ultrafilter over κ and PU is the usual Prikry forcing defined by using U, then a sequence of ordinals αn | n < ω generates a PU-generic object if and only if, for all X ∈ U, we have αn ∈ X for all sufficiently large n < ω.

Slide 11

Slide 11 text

Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters). For example, if U is a normal ultrafilter over κ and PU is the usual Prikry forcing defined by using U, then a sequence of ordinals αn | n < ω generates a PU-generic object if and only if, for all X ∈ U, we have αn ∈ X for all sufficiently large n < ω. In an abstract setting in which we just have models V ⊆ W and a regular cardinal κ in V has been singularized in W , we may not have a normal ultrafilter over κ in V to be diagonalized in W .

Slide 12

Slide 12 text

Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters). For example, if U is a normal ultrafilter over κ and PU is the usual Prikry forcing defined by using U, then a sequence of ordinals αn | n < ω generates a PU-generic object if and only if, for all X ∈ U, we have αn ∈ X for all sufficiently large n < ω. In an abstract setting in which we just have models V ⊆ W and a regular cardinal κ in V has been singularized in W , we may not have a normal ultrafilter over κ in V to be diagonalized in W . There is a natural normal filter over κ to take its place, though: the club filter on κ.

Slide 13

Slide 13 text

Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters). For example, if U is a normal ultrafilter over κ and PU is the usual Prikry forcing defined by using U, then a sequence of ordinals αn | n < ω generates a PU-generic object if and only if, for all X ∈ U, we have αn ∈ X for all sufficiently large n < ω. In an abstract setting in which we just have models V ⊆ W and a regular cardinal κ in V has been singularized in W , we may not have a normal ultrafilter over κ in V to be diagonalized in W . There is a natural normal filter over κ to take its place, though: the club filter on κ. So our pseudo-Prikry sequences will be sequences in W which appropriately diagonalize certain club filters as defined in V .

Slide 14

Slide 14 text

The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ;

Slide 15

Slide 15 text

The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ;

Slide 16

Slide 16 text

The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V ;

Slide 17

Slide 17 text

The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V ; 4 Cα | α < κ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in κ.

Slide 18

Slide 18 text

The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V ; 4 Cα | α < κ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in κ. Then, in W , there is a sequence γi | i < θ of ordinals such that, for all α < κ+ and all sufficiently large i < θ, γi ∈ Cα.

Slide 19

Slide 19 text

The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V ; 4 Cα | α < κ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in κ. Then, in W , there is a sequence γi | i < θ of ordinals such that, for all α < κ+ and all sufficiently large i < θ, γi ∈ Cα. A similar theorem is proven by Gitik [3].

Slide 20

Slide 20 text

Inevitable square sequences Cummings and Schimmerling [1] proved that, if G is a generic filter over V for Prikry forcing at a cardinal κ, then κ,ω holds in V [G].

Slide 21

Slide 21 text

Inevitable square sequences Cummings and Schimmerling [1] proved that, if G is a generic filter over V for Prikry forcing at a cardinal κ, then κ,ω holds in V [G]. It turns out that a pseudo-Prikry sequence as in the Gitik or Dˇ zamonja-Shelah theorems is enough to reach the same conclusion.

Slide 22

Slide 22 text

Inevitable square sequences Cummings and Schimmerling [1] proved that, if G is a generic filter over V for Prikry forcing at a cardinal κ, then κ,ω holds in V [G]. It turns out that a pseudo-Prikry sequence as in the Gitik or Dˇ zamonja-Shelah theorems is enough to reach the same conclusion. Theorem (Gitik, Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, Cummings-Schimmerling) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality ℵ0 in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V .

Slide 23

Slide 23 text

Inevitable square sequences Cummings and Schimmerling [1] proved that, if G is a generic filter over V for Prikry forcing at a cardinal κ, then κ,ω holds in V [G]. It turns out that a pseudo-Prikry sequence as in the Gitik or Dˇ zamonja-Shelah theorems is enough to reach the same conclusion. Theorem (Gitik, Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, Cummings-Schimmerling) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality ℵ0 in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V . Then κ,ω holds in W .

Slide 24

Slide 24 text

A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n).

Slide 25

Slide 25 text

A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ;

Slide 26

Slide 26 text

A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ;

Slide 27

Slide 27 text

A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+n+1)V and (ω1)W < κ;

Slide 28

Slide 28 text

A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+n+1)V and (ω1)W < κ; 4 Dα | α < κ+n+1 ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(κ+n).

Slide 29

Slide 29 text

A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+n+1)V and (ω1)W < κ; 4 Dα | α < κ+n+1 ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Then, in W , there is an increasing sequence xi | i < ω of elements of (Pκ(κ+n))V such that, for all α < κ+n+1 and all sufficiently large i < ω, xi ∈ Dα.

Slide 30

Slide 30 text

A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+n+1)V and (ω1)W < κ; 4 Dα | α < κ+n+1 ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Then, in W , there is an increasing sequence xi | i < ω of elements of (Pκ(κ+n))V such that, for all α < κ+n+1 and all sufficiently large i < ω, xi ∈ Dα. This can be seen as a ”pseudo-” version of a generic sequence for supercompact Prikry forcing using a normal measure on Pκ(κ+n).

Slide 31

Slide 31 text

A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions.

Slide 32

Slide 32 text

A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ;

Slide 33

Slide 33 text

A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ;

Slide 34

Slide 34 text

A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ; 3 in W , there is a sequence Qn | n < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that n<ω Qn = µ;

Slide 35

Slide 35 text

A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ; 3 in W , there is a sequence Qn | n < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that n<ω Qn = µ; 4 in W , µ ≥ (2ω)+ and (µ+)V is a cardinal;

Slide 36

Slide 36 text

A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ; 3 in W , there is a sequence Qn | n < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that n<ω Qn = µ; 4 in W , µ ≥ (2ω)+ and (µ+)V is a cardinal; 5 Dα | α < µ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(µ).

Slide 37

Slide 37 text

A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ; 3 in W , there is a sequence Qn | n < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that n<ω Qn = µ; 4 in W , µ ≥ (2ω)+ and (µ+)V is a cardinal; 5 Dα | α < µ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(µ). Then, in W , there is an increasing sequence xi | i < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that, for all α < µ+ and all sufficiently large i < ω, xi ∈ Dα.

Slide 38

Slide 38 text

II. PCF-theoretic background

Slide 39

Slide 39 text

<∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ.

Slide 40

Slide 40 text

<∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way.

Slide 41

Slide 41 text

<∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way. Definition (Exact upper bound) Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a <∗-increasing sequence of elements of θOn.

Slide 42

Slide 42 text

<∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way. Definition (Exact upper bound) Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a <∗-increasing sequence of elements of θOn. A function g ∈ θOn is an exact upper bound (e.u.b.) for f if

Slide 43

Slide 43 text

<∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way. Definition (Exact upper bound) Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a <∗-increasing sequence of elements of θOn. A function g ∈ θOn is an exact upper bound (e.u.b.) for f if 1 fα <∗ g for all α < λ;

Slide 44

Slide 44 text

<∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way. Definition (Exact upper bound) Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a <∗-increasing sequence of elements of θOn. A function g ∈ θOn is an exact upper bound (e.u.b.) for f if 1 fα <∗ g for all α < λ; 2 for every function h ∈ θOn, if h <∗ g, then there is α < λ such that h < fα.

Slide 45

Slide 45 text

Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ.

Slide 46

Slide 46 text

Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ. A sequence f = fα | α < λ of functions in i

Slide 47

Slide 47 text

Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ. A sequence f = fα | α < λ of functions in i

Slide 48

Slide 48 text

Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ. A sequence f = fα | α < λ of functions in i

Slide 49

Slide 49 text

Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ. A sequence f = fα | α < λ of functions in i

Slide 50

Slide 50 text

Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if

Slide 51

Slide 51 text

Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if 1 f is <∗-increasing;

Slide 52

Slide 52 text

Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if 1 f is <∗-increasing; 2 for every limit ordinal γ < λ, there is a club D ⊆ γ and an i < θ such that fα

Slide 53

Slide 53 text

Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if 1 f is <∗-increasing; 2 for every limit ordinal γ < λ, there is a club D ⊆ γ and an i < θ such that fα

Slide 54

Slide 54 text

Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if 1 f is <∗-increasing; 2 for every limit ordinal γ < λ, there is a club D ⊆ γ and an i < θ such that fα ν for all i < θ.

Slide 55

Slide 55 text

III. Diagonal pseudo-Prikry sequences

Slide 56

Slide 56 text

Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail.

Slide 57

Slide 57 text

Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing.

Slide 58

Slide 58 text

Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing. But we’ve seen that this necessarily forces κ,ω to hold.

Slide 59

Slide 59 text

Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing. But we’ve seen that this necessarily forces κ,ω to hold. By a generalization of this result due to Magidor and Sinapova, κ,ω will hold in any extension W in which • (κ+)W is the successor of a regular cardinal in V ;

Slide 60

Slide 60 text

Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing. But we’ve seen that this necessarily forces κ,ω to hold. By a generalization of this result due to Magidor and Sinapova, κ,ω will hold in any extension W in which • (κ+)W is the successor of a regular cardinal in V ; • every V -regular cardinal in the interval [κ, (κ+)V ) has countable cofinality in W .

Slide 61

Slide 61 text

Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing. But we’ve seen that this necessarily forces κ,ω to hold. By a generalization of this result due to Magidor and Sinapova, κ,ω will hold in any extension W in which • (κ+)W is the successor of a regular cardinal in V ; • every V -regular cardinal in the interval [κ, (κ+)V ) has countable cofinality in W . This might lead us to look for Prikry-type extensions W in which (κ+)W is the successor of a singular cardinal in V .

Slide 62

Slide 62 text

Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing.

Slide 63

Slide 63 text

Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω.

Slide 64

Slide 64 text

Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω;

Slide 65

Slide 65 text

Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω.

Slide 66

Slide 66 text

Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω. As a result, in V P, cf((κ+n)V ) = ω for all n < ω.

Slide 67

Slide 67 text

Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω. As a result, in V P, cf((κ+n)V ) = ω for all n < ω. κ remains a cardinal, and (κ+)V P = (κ+ω+1)V .

Slide 68

Slide 68 text

Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω. As a result, in V P, cf((κ+n)V ) = ω for all n < ω. κ remains a cardinal, and (κ+)V P = (κ+ω+1)V . Moreover, APκ (and hence κ,ω) fails in V P.

Slide 69

Slide 69 text

Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω. As a result, in V P, cf((κ+n)V ) = ω for all n < ω. κ remains a cardinal, and (κ+)V P = (κ+ω+1)V . Moreover, APκ (and hence κ,ω) fails in V P. If 2κ = κ+ω+2 in V , then SCH fails at κ in V P as well.

Slide 70

Slide 70 text

Meeting diagonal clubs

Slide 71

Slide 71 text

Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ.

Slide 72

Slide 72 text

Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ).

Slide 73

Slide 73 text

Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ). Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in V , µ is a singular cardinal, cf(µ) = θ, and µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ.

Slide 74

Slide 74 text

Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ). Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in V , µ is a singular cardinal, cf(µ) = θ, and µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose moreover that, in W , (µ+)V is the successor of a singular cardinal ν of cofinality θ and cf(µi ) = θ for all i < θ.

Slide 75

Slide 75 text

Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ). Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in V , µ is a singular cardinal, cf(µ) = θ, and µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose moreover that, in W , (µ+)V is the successor of a singular cardinal ν of cofinality θ and cf(µi ) = θ for all i < θ. Then, in W , there is a function g ∈ µ such that, for every diagonal club in µ, Di | i < θ ∈ V , we have g(i) ∈ Di for all sufficiently large i < θ.

Slide 76

Slide 76 text

Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ). Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in V , µ is a singular cardinal, cf(µ) = θ, and µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose moreover that, in W , (µ+)V is the successor of a singular cardinal ν of cofinality θ and cf(µi ) = θ for all i < θ. Then, in W , there is a function g ∈ µ such that, for every diagonal club in µ, Di | i < θ ∈ V , we have g(i) ∈ Di for all sufficiently large i < θ. Also, we can require sup{cf(g(i)) | i < θ} = ν.

Slide 77

Slide 77 text

Proof

Slide 78

Slide 78 text

More proof

Slide 79

Slide 79 text

Still more proof

Slide 80

Slide 80 text

This proof isn’t over yet?

Slide 81

Slide 81 text

A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W .

Slide 82

Slide 82 text

A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals.

Slide 83

Slide 83 text

A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals. Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in both V and W , µ is a singular cardinal of cofinality θ.

Slide 84

Slide 84 text

A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals. Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in both V and W , µ is a singular cardinal of cofinality θ. Suppose also that, in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ.

Slide 85

Slide 85 text

A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals. Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in both V and W , µ is a singular cardinal of cofinality θ. Suppose also that, in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose finally that (µ+)V = (µ+)W and ( µ)V is bounded in (( µ)W , <∗).

Slide 86

Slide 86 text

A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals. Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in both V and W , µ is a singular cardinal of cofinality θ. Suppose also that, in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose finally that (µ+)V = (µ+)W and ( µ)V is bounded in (( µ)W , <∗). Then, in W , there is a function g ∈ µ such that, for every diagonal club in µ, Di | i < θ ∈ V , we have g(i) ∈ Di for all sufficiently large i < θ. Also, we can require that sup{cf(g(i)) | i < θ} = µ.

Slide 87

Slide 87 text

Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ;

Slide 88

Slide 88 text

Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit;

Slide 89

Slide 89 text

Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0;

Slide 90

Slide 90 text

Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0; 4 in W , there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(µ))V such that i<θ xi = µ;

Slide 91

Slide 91 text

Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0; 4 in W , there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(µ))V such that i<θ xi = µ; 5 in W , (µ+)V remains a cardinal and µ ≥ 2θ;

Slide 92

Slide 92 text

Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0; 4 in W , there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(µ))V such that i<θ xi = µ; 5 in W , (µ+)V remains a cardinal and µ ≥ 2θ; 6 in V , D(α) | α < µ+ is a sequence of diagonal clubs in Pκ(µ).

Slide 93

Slide 93 text

Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0; 4 in W , there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(µ))V such that i<θ xi = µ; 5 in W , (µ+)V remains a cardinal and µ ≥ 2θ; 6 in V , D(α) | α < µ+ is a sequence of diagonal clubs in Pκ(µ). Then, in W , there is yi | i < θ such that, for all α < µ+ and all sufficiently large i < θ, yi ∈ D(α)i .

Slide 94

Slide 94 text

IV. Fat trees and pseudo-Prikry sequences

Slide 95

Slide 95 text

A new proof

Slide 96

Slide 96 text

More new proof

Slide 97

Slide 97 text

Still more new proof

Slide 98

Slide 98 text

This had better be the end of the new proof

Slide 99

Slide 99 text

Fat trees Definition Suppose that κ is a regular, uncountable cardinal, n < ω, and, for all m ≤ n, λm ≥ κ is a regular cardinal. Then T ⊆ k≤n+1 m

Slide 100

Slide 100 text

Fat trees Definition Suppose that κ is a regular, uncountable cardinal, n < ω, and, for all m ≤ n, λm ≥ κ is a regular cardinal. Then T ⊆ k≤n+1 m

Slide 101

Slide 101 text

Fat trees Definition Suppose that κ is a regular, uncountable cardinal, n < ω, and, for all m ≤ n, λm ≥ κ is a regular cardinal. Then T ⊆ k≤n+1 m

Slide 102

Slide 102 text

Fat trees Definition Suppose that κ is a regular, uncountable cardinal, n < ω, and, for all m ≤ n, λm ≥ κ is a regular cardinal. Then T ⊆ k≤n+1 m

Slide 103

Slide 103 text

Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ;

Slide 104

Slide 104 text

Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular;

Slide 105

Slide 105 text

Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular; 3 in W , θ < θ+2 < |κ|, θ is a regular cardinal, and there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(λ))V such that i<θ xi = λ;

Slide 106

Slide 106 text

Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular; 3 in W , θ < θ+2 < |κ|, θ is a regular cardinal, and there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(λ))V such that i<θ xi = λ; 4 (λ+)V remains a cardinal in W ;

Slide 107

Slide 107 text

Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular; 3 in W , θ < θ+2 < |κ|, θ is a regular cardinal, and there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(λ))V such that i<θ xi = λ; 4 (λ+)V remains a cardinal in W ; 5 n < ω and, in V , λi | i ≤ n is a sequence of regular cardinals from [κ, λ] and T(α) | α < λ+ is a sequence of fat trees of type (κ, λ0, . . . , λn ).

Slide 108

Slide 108 text

Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular; 3 in W , θ < θ+2 < |κ|, θ is a regular cardinal, and there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(λ))V such that i<θ xi = λ; 4 (λ+)V remains a cardinal in W ; 5 n < ω and, in V , λi | i ≤ n is a sequence of regular cardinals from [κ, λ] and T(α) | α < λ+ is a sequence of fat trees of type (κ, λ0, . . . , λn ). Then, in W , there is a sequence σi | i < θ such that, for all α < λ+ and all sufficiently large i < θ, σi is a maximal element of T(α).

Slide 109

Slide 109 text

Some remarks The proof of the theorem on the previous slide is an elaboration of the proof presented at the beginning of this section.

Slide 110

Slide 110 text

Some remarks The proof of the theorem on the previous slide is an elaboration of the proof presented at the beginning of this section. The theorem yields as special cases all of the results mentioned in the first section of this talk (though requiring very slightly stronger hypotheses in some cases).

Slide 111

Slide 111 text

Some remarks The proof of the theorem on the previous slide is an elaboration of the proof presented at the beginning of this section. The theorem yields as special cases all of the results mentioned in the first section of this talk (though requiring very slightly stronger hypotheses in some cases). Questions remain about the extent to which the hypotheses of these results necessarily hold in outer models in which cardinals have been singularized.

Slide 112

Slide 112 text

Some remarks The proof of the theorem on the previous slide is an elaboration of the proof presented at the beginning of this section. The theorem yields as special cases all of the results mentioned in the first section of this talk (though requiring very slightly stronger hypotheses in some cases). Questions remain about the extent to which the hypotheses of these results necessarily hold in outer models in which cardinals have been singularized. Conjecture (Gitik) Suppose that V is an inner model of W , κ is regular in V , (cf(κ))W = ω, (ℵ1)V = (ℵ1)W , and V and W agree about a final segment of cardinals. Then there is an inner model V ⊆ V such that W contains a sequence that is generic over V for Namba forcing, stationary tower forcing, or a Prikry-type forcing.

Slide 113

Slide 113 text

References James Cummings and Ernest Schimmerling, Indexed squares, Israel J. Math. 131 (2002), 61–99. MR 1942302 Mirna Dˇ zamonja and Saharon Shelah, On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I

Slide 114

Slide 114 text

All artwork by Victor Vasarely.

Slide 115

Slide 115 text

Thank you!