Upgrade to Pro — share decks privately, control downloads, hide ads and more …

Pseudo-Prikry sequences

Pseudo-Prikry sequences

Chris Lambie-Hanson

February 23, 2021
Tweet

More Decks by Chris Lambie-Hanson

Other Decks in Research

Transcript

  1. Pseudo-Prikry Sequences Chris Lambie-Hanson Department of Mathematics and Applied Mathematics

    Virginia Commonwealth University Prikry Forcing Online 14 December 2020
  2. The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools

    for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors.
  3. The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools

    for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors. In the last 30 years, some results have given some indication about why this might be the case.
  4. The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools

    for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors. In the last 30 years, some results have given some indication about why this might be the case. These results all have the following flavor:
  5. The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools

    for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors. In the last 30 years, some results have given some indication about why this might be the case. These results all have the following flavor: If V is an inner model of W and there is a regular cardinal in V that is singular in W (and certain other cardinals are preserved from V to W ), then there is an object in W that resembles a generic object over V for some Prikry- type forcing.
  6. The basic premise Prikry-type forcings have been uniquely effective tools

    for proving consistency results about cardinal arithmetic and combinatorics at singular cardinals and their successors. In the last 30 years, some results have given some indication about why this might be the case. These results all have the following flavor: If V is an inner model of W and there is a regular cardinal in V that is singular in W (and certain other cardinals are preserved from V to W ), then there is an object in W that resembles a generic object over V for some Prikry- type forcing. We call such objects pseudo-Prikry sequences.
  7. Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects

    is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters).
  8. Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects

    is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters). For example, if U is a normal ultrafilter over κ and PU is the usual Prikry forcing defined by using U, then a sequence of ordinals αn | n < ω generates a PU-generic object if and only if, for all X ∈ U, we have αn ∈ X for all sufficiently large n < ω.
  9. Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects

    is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters). For example, if U is a normal ultrafilter over κ and PU is the usual Prikry forcing defined by using U, then a sequence of ordinals αn | n < ω generates a PU-generic object if and only if, for all X ∈ U, we have αn ∈ X for all sufficiently large n < ω. In an abstract setting in which we just have models V ⊆ W and a regular cardinal κ in V has been singularized in W , we may not have a normal ultrafilter over κ in V to be diagonalized in W .
  10. Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects

    is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters). For example, if U is a normal ultrafilter over κ and PU is the usual Prikry forcing defined by using U, then a sequence of ordinals αn | n < ω generates a PU-generic object if and only if, for all X ∈ U, we have αn ∈ X for all sufficiently large n < ω. In an abstract setting in which we just have models V ⊆ W and a regular cardinal κ in V has been singularized in W , we may not have a normal ultrafilter over κ in V to be diagonalized in W . There is a natural normal filter over κ to take its place, though: the club filter on κ.
  11. Diagonalization A key property of generic objects for Prikry-type objects

    is that they diagonalize some ground model ultrafilter (or sequence of ultrafilters). For example, if U is a normal ultrafilter over κ and PU is the usual Prikry forcing defined by using U, then a sequence of ordinals αn | n < ω generates a PU-generic object if and only if, for all X ∈ U, we have αn ∈ X for all sufficiently large n < ω. In an abstract setting in which we just have models V ⊆ W and a regular cardinal κ in V has been singularized in W , we may not have a normal ultrafilter over κ in V to be diagonalized in W . There is a natural normal filter over κ to take its place, though: the club filter on κ. So our pseudo-Prikry sequences will be sequences in W which appropriately diagonalize certain club filters as defined in V .
  12. The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that:

    1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ;
  13. The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that:

    1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V ;
  14. The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that:

    1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V ; 4 Cα | α < κ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in κ.
  15. The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that:

    1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V ; 4 Cα | α < κ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in κ. Then, in W , there is a sequence γi | i < θ of ordinals such that, for all α < κ+ and all sufficiently large i < θ, γi ∈ Cα.
  16. The earliest results Theorem (Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, ‘95, [2]) Suppose that:

    1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality θ in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V ; 4 Cα | α < κ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in κ. Then, in W , there is a sequence γi | i < θ of ordinals such that, for all α < κ+ and all sufficiently large i < θ, γi ∈ Cα. A similar theorem is proven by Gitik [3].
  17. Inevitable square sequences Cummings and Schimmerling [1] proved that, if

    G is a generic filter over V for Prikry forcing at a cardinal κ, then κ,ω holds in V [G].
  18. Inevitable square sequences Cummings and Schimmerling [1] proved that, if

    G is a generic filter over V for Prikry forcing at a cardinal κ, then κ,ω holds in V [G]. It turns out that a pseudo-Prikry sequence as in the Gitik or Dˇ zamonja-Shelah theorems is enough to reach the same conclusion.
  19. Inevitable square sequences Cummings and Schimmerling [1] proved that, if

    G is a generic filter over V for Prikry forcing at a cardinal κ, then κ,ω holds in V [G]. It turns out that a pseudo-Prikry sequence as in the Gitik or Dˇ zamonja-Shelah theorems is enough to reach the same conclusion. Theorem (Gitik, Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, Cummings-Schimmerling) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality ℵ0 in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V .
  20. Inevitable square sequences Cummings and Schimmerling [1] proved that, if

    G is a generic filter over V for Prikry forcing at a cardinal κ, then κ,ω holds in V [G]. It turns out that a pseudo-Prikry sequence as in the Gitik or Dˇ zamonja-Shelah theorems is enough to reach the same conclusion. Theorem (Gitik, Dˇ zamonja-Shelah, Cummings-Schimmerling) Suppose that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is an inaccessible cardinal in V and a singular cardinal of cofinality ℵ0 in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+)V . Then κ,ω holds in W .
  21. A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah

    result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n).
  22. A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah

    result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ;
  23. A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah

    result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ;
  24. A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah

    result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+n+1)V and (ω1)W < κ;
  25. A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah

    result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+n+1)V and (ω1)W < κ; 4 Dα | α < κ+n+1 ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(κ+n).
  26. A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah

    result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+n+1)V and (ω1)W < κ; 4 Dα | α < κ+n+1 ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Then, in W , there is an increasing sequence xi | i < ω of elements of (Pκ(κ+n))V such that, for all α < κ+n+1 and all sufficiently large i < ω, xi ∈ Dα.
  27. A two-cardinal generalization Magidor and Sinapova generalize the D˘ zamonja-Shelah

    result in two ways, including the following extension to clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Theorem (Magidor-Sinapova, ’17, [6]) Suppose that n < ω and: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 κ is a regular cardinal in V and, for all m ≤ n, (κ+m)V has countable cofinality in W ; 3 (κ+)W = (κ+n+1)V and (ω1)W < κ; 4 Dα | α < κ+n+1 ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(κ+n). Then, in W , there is an increasing sequence xi | i < ω of elements of (Pκ(κ+n))V such that, for all α < κ+n+1 and all sufficiently large i < ω, xi ∈ Dα. This can be seen as a ”pseudo-” version of a generic sequence for supercompact Prikry forcing using a normal measure on Pκ(κ+n).
  28. A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general

    setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions.
  29. A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general

    setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ;
  30. A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general

    setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ;
  31. A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general

    setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ; 3 in W , there is a sequence Qn | n < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that n<ω Qn = µ;
  32. A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general

    setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ; 3 in W , there is a sequence Qn | n < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that n<ω Qn = µ; 4 in W , µ ≥ (2ω)+ and (µ+)V is a cardinal;
  33. A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general

    setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ; 3 in W , there is a sequence Qn | n < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that n<ω Qn = µ; 4 in W , µ ≥ (2ω)+ and (µ+)V is a cardinal; 5 Dα | α < µ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(µ).
  34. A further extension Gitik extends this result to the general

    setting of Pκ(µ), under some additional cardinal arithmetic assumptions. Theorem (Gitik, ’18, [4]) Suppose that 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ < µ are regular cardinals and µ<µ = µ; 3 in W , there is a sequence Qn | n < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that n<ω Qn = µ; 4 in W , µ ≥ (2ω)+ and (µ+)V is a cardinal; 5 Dα | α < µ+ ∈ V is a sequence of clubs in Pκ(µ). Then, in W , there is an increasing sequence xi | i < ω of elements of (Pκ(µ))V such that, for all α < µ+ and all sufficiently large i < ω, xi ∈ Dα.
  35. <∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal

    and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ.
  36. <∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal

    and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way.
  37. <∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal

    and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way. Definition (Exact upper bound) Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a <∗-increasing sequence of elements of θOn.
  38. <∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal

    and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way. Definition (Exact upper bound) Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a <∗-increasing sequence of elements of θOn. A function g ∈ θOn is an exact upper bound (e.u.b.) for f if
  39. <∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal

    and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way. Definition (Exact upper bound) Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a <∗-increasing sequence of elements of θOn. A function g ∈ θOn is an exact upper bound (e.u.b.) for f if 1 fα <∗ g for all α < λ;
  40. <∗-increasing sequences Definition Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal

    and f , g ∈ θOn. Then f <∗ g if {i < θ | g(i) ≤ f (i)} is bounded in θ. Expressions such as f ≤∗ g and f =∗ g are defined in the obvious way. Definition (Exact upper bound) Suppose that θ is a regular cardinal and f = fα | α < λ is a <∗-increasing sequence of elements of θOn. A function g ∈ θOn is an exact upper bound (e.u.b.) for f if 1 fα <∗ g for all α < λ; 2 for every function h ∈ θOn, if h <∗ g, then there is α < λ such that h < fα.
  41. Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and

    µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ.
  42. Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and

    µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ. A sequence f = fα | α < λ of functions in i<cf(µ) µi is called a scale (of length λ) in i<cf(µ) µi if
  43. Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and

    µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ. A sequence f = fα | α < λ of functions in i<cf(µ) µi is called a scale (of length λ) in i<cf(µ) µi if 1 f is <∗-increasing;
  44. Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and

    µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ. A sequence f = fα | α < λ of functions in i<cf(µ) µi is called a scale (of length λ) in i<cf(µ) µi if 1 f is <∗-increasing; 2 for all h ∈ i<cf(µ) µi , there is α < λ such that h <∗ fα.
  45. Scales Definition Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal and

    µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ. A sequence f = fα | α < λ of functions in i<cf(µ) µi is called a scale (of length λ) in i<cf(µ) µi if 1 f is <∗-increasing; 2 for all h ∈ i<cf(µ) µi , there is α < λ such that h <∗ fα. Theorem (Shelah) Suppose that µ is a singular cardinal. Then there is an increasing sequence µi | i < cf(µ) of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, such that there is a scale of length µ+ in i<cf(µ) µi .
  46. Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and

    f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if
  47. Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and

    f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if 1 f is <∗-increasing;
  48. Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and

    f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if 1 f is <∗-increasing; 2 for every limit ordinal γ < λ, there is a club D ⊆ γ and an i < θ such that fα <i fγ for all α ∈ D.
  49. Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and

    f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if 1 f is <∗-increasing; 2 for every limit ordinal γ < λ, there is a club D ⊆ γ and an i < θ such that fα <i fγ for all α ∈ D. Theorem Suppose that θ < ν < ν++ < λ are regular cardinals and f is a club-increasing sequence of length λ, consisting of elements of θOn.
  50. Club-increasing sequences Definition If θ is a regular cardinal and

    f = fα | α < λ is a sequence of elements of θOn, we say that f is club-increasing if 1 f is <∗-increasing; 2 for every limit ordinal γ < λ, there is a club D ⊆ γ and an i < θ such that fα <i fγ for all α ∈ D. Theorem Suppose that θ < ν < ν++ < λ are regular cardinals and f is a club-increasing sequence of length λ, consisting of elements of θOn. Then there is an e.u.b. g for f such that cf(g(i)) > ν for all i < θ.
  51. Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with

    a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail.
  52. Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with

    a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing.
  53. Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with

    a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing. But we’ve seen that this necessarily forces κ,ω to hold.
  54. Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with

    a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing. But we’ve seen that this necessarily forces κ,ω to hold. By a generalization of this result due to Magidor and Sinapova, κ,ω will hold in any extension W in which • (κ+)W is the successor of a regular cardinal in V ;
  55. Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with

    a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing. But we’ve seen that this necessarily forces κ,ω to hold. By a generalization of this result due to Magidor and Sinapova, κ,ω will hold in any extension W in which • (κ+)W is the successor of a regular cardinal in V ; • every V -regular cardinal in the interval [κ, (κ+)V ) has countable cofinality in W .
  56. Avoiding squares Suppose one wants to find a model with

    a singular cardinal κ of countable cofinality at which both SCH and κ,ω fail. The simplest way to obtain a failure of SCH is to start with a measurable cardinal κ at which GCH fails and do Prikry forcing. But we’ve seen that this necessarily forces κ,ω to hold. By a generalization of this result due to Magidor and Sinapova, κ,ω will hold in any extension W in which • (κ+)W is the successor of a regular cardinal in V ; • every V -regular cardinal in the interval [κ, (κ+)V ) has countable cofinality in W . This might lead us to look for Prikry-type extensions W in which (κ+)W is the successor of a singular cardinal in V .
  57. Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and

    Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing.
  58. Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and

    Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω.
  59. Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and

    Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω;
  60. Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and

    Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω.
  61. Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and

    Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω. As a result, in V P, cf((κ+n)V ) = ω for all n < ω.
  62. Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and

    Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω. As a result, in V P, cf((κ+n)V ) = ω for all n < ω. κ remains a cardinal, and (κ+)V P = (κ+ω+1)V .
  63. Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and

    Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω. As a result, in V P, cf((κ+n)V ) = ω for all n < ω. κ remains a cardinal, and (κ+)V P = (κ+ω+1)V . Moreover, APκ (and hence κ,ω) fails in V P.
  64. Diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing Solving this problem led Gitik and

    Sharon to introduce diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing. Suppose that κ is a supercompact cardinal, U∗ is a supercompactness measure on Pκ(κ+ω+1), and Un is the projection of U∗ on Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω. The diagonal supercompact Prikry forcing P associated to Un | n < ω introduces an increasing sequence xn | n < ω such that • xn ∈ Pκ(κ+n) for all n < ω; • for every sequence Xn | n < ω ∈ V such that Xn ∈ Un for all n < ω, we have xn ∈ Xn for all sufficiently large n < ω. As a result, in V P, cf((κ+n)V ) = ω for all n < ω. κ remains a cardinal, and (κ+)V P = (κ+ω+1)V . Moreover, APκ (and hence κ,ω) fails in V P. If 2κ = κ+ω+2 in V , then SCH fails at κ in V P as well.
  65. Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular

    cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ.
  66. Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular

    cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ).
  67. Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular

    cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ). Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in V , µ is a singular cardinal, cf(µ) = θ, and µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ.
  68. Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular

    cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ). Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in V , µ is a singular cardinal, cf(µ) = θ, and µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose moreover that, in W , (µ+)V is the successor of a singular cardinal ν of cofinality θ and cf(µi ) = θ for all i < θ.
  69. Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular

    cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ). Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in V , µ is a singular cardinal, cf(µ) = θ, and µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose moreover that, in W , (µ+)V is the successor of a singular cardinal ν of cofinality θ and cf(µi ) = θ for all i < θ. Then, in W , there is a function g ∈ µ such that, for every diagonal club in µ, Di | i < θ ∈ V , we have g(i) ∈ Di for all sufficiently large i < θ.
  70. Meeting diagonal clubs Definition Suppose that µ is a singular

    cardinal and µ = µi | i < cf(µ) is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ. A diagonal club in µ is a sequence Di | i < cf(µ) such that Di is a club in µi for all i < cf(µ). Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in V , µ is a singular cardinal, cf(µ) = θ, and µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose moreover that, in W , (µ+)V is the successor of a singular cardinal ν of cofinality θ and cf(µi ) = θ for all i < θ. Then, in W , there is a function g ∈ µ such that, for every diagonal club in µ, Di | i < θ ∈ V , we have g(i) ∈ Di for all sufficiently large i < θ. Also, we can require sup{cf(g(i)) | i < θ} = ν.
  71. A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous

    proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W .
  72. A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous

    proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals.
  73. A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous

    proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals. Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in both V and W , µ is a singular cardinal of cofinality θ.
  74. A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous

    proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals. Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in both V and W , µ is a singular cardinal of cofinality θ. Suppose also that, in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ.
  75. A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous

    proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals. Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in both V and W , µ is a singular cardinal of cofinality θ. Suppose also that, in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose finally that (µ+)V = (µ+)W and ( µ)V is bounded in (( µ)W , <∗).
  76. A variant Notice that the essential point in the previous

    proof was the fact that the ground-model scale was bounded by a function in µ in W . This leads to the following variant, which doesn’t require any singularizing of cardinals. Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose that V is an inner model of W and, in both V and W , µ is a singular cardinal of cofinality θ. Suppose also that, in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in µ such that there is a scale of length µ+ in µ. Suppose finally that (µ+)V = (µ+)W and ( µ)V is bounded in (( µ)W , <∗). Then, in W , there is a function g ∈ µ such that, for every diagonal club in µ, Di | i < θ ∈ V , we have g(i) ∈ Di for all sufficiently large i < θ. Also, we can require that sup{cf(g(i)) | i < θ} = µ.
  77. Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1

    V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit;
  78. Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1

    V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0;
  79. Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1

    V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0; 4 in W , there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(µ))V such that i<θ xi = µ;
  80. Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1

    V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0; 4 in W , there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(µ))V such that i<θ xi = µ; 5 in W , (µ+)V remains a cardinal and µ ≥ 2θ;
  81. Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1

    V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0; 4 in W , there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(µ))V such that i<θ xi = µ; 5 in W , (µ+)V remains a cardinal and µ ≥ 2θ; 6 in V , D(α) | α < µ+ is a sequence of diagonal clubs in Pκ(µ).
  82. Generalized diagonal sequences Theorem (LH, ‘18, [5]) Suppose that: 1

    V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , cf(µ) = θ < κ = cf(κ) < µ are cardinals, with µ strong limit; 3 in V , µ = µi | i < θ is an increasing sequence of regular cardinals, cofinal in µ, with κ ≤ µ0; 4 in W , there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(µ))V such that i<θ xi = µ; 5 in W , (µ+)V remains a cardinal and µ ≥ 2θ; 6 in V , D(α) | α < µ+ is a sequence of diagonal clubs in Pκ(µ). Then, in W , there is yi | i < θ such that, for all α < µ+ and all sufficiently large i < θ, yi ∈ D(α)i .
  83. Fat trees Definition Suppose that κ is a regular, uncountable

    cardinal, n < ω, and, for all m ≤ n, λm ≥ κ is a regular cardinal. Then T ⊆ k≤n+1 m<k λm is a fat tree of type (κ, λ0 , . . . , λn ) if:
  84. Fat trees Definition Suppose that κ is a regular, uncountable

    cardinal, n < ω, and, for all m ≤ n, λm ≥ κ is a regular cardinal. Then T ⊆ k≤n+1 m<k λm is a fat tree of type (κ, λ0 , . . . , λn ) if: 1 for all σ ∈ T and < lh(σ), we have σ ∈ T;
  85. Fat trees Definition Suppose that κ is a regular, uncountable

    cardinal, n < ω, and, for all m ≤ n, λm ≥ κ is a regular cardinal. Then T ⊆ k≤n+1 m<k λm is a fat tree of type (κ, λ0 , . . . , λn ) if: 1 for all σ ∈ T and < lh(σ), we have σ ∈ T; 2 for all σ ∈ T such that k := lh(σ) ≤ n, succT (σ) := {α | σ α ∈ T} is (< κ)-club in λk .
  86. Fat trees Definition Suppose that κ is a regular, uncountable

    cardinal, n < ω, and, for all m ≤ n, λm ≥ κ is a regular cardinal. Then T ⊆ k≤n+1 m<k λm is a fat tree of type (κ, λ0 , . . . , λn ) if: 1 for all σ ∈ T and < lh(σ), we have σ ∈ T; 2 for all σ ∈ T such that k := lh(σ) ≤ n, succT (σ) := {α | σ α ∈ T} is (< κ)-club in λk . Lemma If C is a club in Pκ (κ+n), then there is a fat tree of type (κ, κ+n, κ+n−1, . . . , κ ) such that, for every maximal σ ∈ T, there is x ∈ C such that, for all m ≤ n, sup(x ∩ κ+m) = σ(n − m).
  87. Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose

    that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular;
  88. Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose

    that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular; 3 in W , θ < θ+2 < |κ|, θ is a regular cardinal, and there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(λ))V such that i<θ xi = λ;
  89. Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose

    that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular; 3 in W , θ < θ+2 < |κ|, θ is a regular cardinal, and there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(λ))V such that i<θ xi = λ; 4 (λ+)V remains a cardinal in W ;
  90. Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose

    that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular; 3 in W , θ < θ+2 < |κ|, θ is a regular cardinal, and there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(λ))V such that i<θ xi = λ; 4 (λ+)V remains a cardinal in W ; 5 n < ω and, in V , λi | i ≤ n is a sequence of regular cardinals from [κ, λ] and T(α) | α < λ+ is a sequence of fat trees of type (κ, λ0, . . . , λn ).
  91. Outside guessing of fat trees Theorem (LH, ’18, [5]) Suppose

    that: 1 V is an inner model of W ; 2 in V , κ ≤ λ are cardinals, with κ regular; 3 in W , θ < θ+2 < |κ|, θ is a regular cardinal, and there is a ⊆-increasing sequence xi | i < θ from (Pκ(λ))V such that i<θ xi = λ; 4 (λ+)V remains a cardinal in W ; 5 n < ω and, in V , λi | i ≤ n is a sequence of regular cardinals from [κ, λ] and T(α) | α < λ+ is a sequence of fat trees of type (κ, λ0, . . . , λn ). Then, in W , there is a sequence σi | i < θ such that, for all α < λ+ and all sufficiently large i < θ, σi is a maximal element of T(α).
  92. Some remarks The proof of the theorem on the previous

    slide is an elaboration of the proof presented at the beginning of this section.
  93. Some remarks The proof of the theorem on the previous

    slide is an elaboration of the proof presented at the beginning of this section. The theorem yields as special cases all of the results mentioned in the first section of this talk (though requiring very slightly stronger hypotheses in some cases).
  94. Some remarks The proof of the theorem on the previous

    slide is an elaboration of the proof presented at the beginning of this section. The theorem yields as special cases all of the results mentioned in the first section of this talk (though requiring very slightly stronger hypotheses in some cases). Questions remain about the extent to which the hypotheses of these results necessarily hold in outer models in which cardinals have been singularized.
  95. Some remarks The proof of the theorem on the previous

    slide is an elaboration of the proof presented at the beginning of this section. The theorem yields as special cases all of the results mentioned in the first section of this talk (though requiring very slightly stronger hypotheses in some cases). Questions remain about the extent to which the hypotheses of these results necessarily hold in outer models in which cardinals have been singularized. Conjecture (Gitik) Suppose that V is an inner model of W , κ is regular in V , (cf(κ))W = ω, (ℵ1)V = (ℵ1)W , and V and W agree about a final segment of cardinals. Then there is an inner model V ⊆ V such that W contains a sequence that is generic over V for Namba forcing, stationary tower forcing, or a Prikry-type forcing.
  96. References James Cummings and Ernest Schimmerling, Indexed squares, Israel J.

    Math. 131 (2002), 61–99. MR 1942302 Mirna Dˇ zamonja and Saharon Shelah, On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I<f [λ], Fund. Math. 148 (1995), no. 2, 165–198. MR 1360144 Moti Gitik, Some results on the nonstationary ideal II, Israel J. Math. 99 (1997), 175–188. MR 1469092 , A note on sequences witnessing singularity, following Magidor and Sinapova, Math. Log. Q. 64 (2018), no. 3, 249–253. Chris Lambie-Hanson, Pseudo-Prikry sequences, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 146 (2018), no. 11, 4905–4920. Menachem Magidor and Dima Sinapova, Singular cardinals and square properties, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 145 (2017), no. 11, 4971–4980.