Upgrade to Pro — share decks privately, control downloads, hide ads and more …

Recognition, Ideology, and Critique

Recognition, Ideology, and Critique

Paper given at Workshop "Ambivalence of Recognition"

Titus Stahl

April 04, 2013
Tweet

More Decks by Titus Stahl

Other Decks in Research

Transcript

  1. Recognition, Ideology, and Critique
    Titus Stahl
    Goethe University Frankfurt

    View Slide

  2. The issue
    Relationship between theories of recognition and models of
    critique
    Challenge of pessimist theories of recognition to a
    recognition-based model of social critique

    View Slide

  3. The argument
    (1) Recognition as a basis for critique - the optimist tradition and
    the challenge of ideological recognition
    (2) The failure of pessimism as a model of critique
    (3) Hegelian replies
    (4) A new start: ideology as a second-order feature of subjectivating
    practices of recognition

    View Slide

  4. Optimist and pessimist theories of recognition

    View Slide

  5. Optimism (1)
    A first optimist tradition: Recognition as basis of a vocabulary for
    reconstructing the justification of social and political demands and
    struggles.
    Model of critique: Social-historical immanent critique - employing
    the “normative surplus” of spheres of recognition to reconstruct
    justification of demands for progress.

    View Slide

  6. Optimism (2)
    A second optimist tradition: Neo-Hegelianism. Recognition as
    necessary for normative, discursive practices and for the possibility of
    there being subjects (subject as a normative status).
    (Implicit) model of critique: All normative demands, in virtue of
    their claims to justification, depend in their force on practices of
    recognition.

    View Slide

  7. Pessimism (1)
    Althusser: Recognition as ideology, subjecitivity bound to
    interpellation by ideological apparatuses and to acceptance of that
    interpellation by subjects.

    View Slide

  8. Pessimism (2)
    Potential problem for critique: If subjects are ontologically
    dependent on a prior submission to specific norms of recognition, a
    model of critique which reconstructs the demands of critique as
    expressing normative claims put forward by subjects constitutively
    cannot go beyond the norms of recognition.

    View Slide

  9. Pessimism (3)
    One potential consequence: Giving up on the project of a
    normative critique altogether.

    View Slide

  10. Pessimism (4)
    Butler: Combination of social ontological with normative and
    epistemic skepticism.
    Normative skepticism: Normative dependence of critique on
    subjectivating recognition might require a normative legitimization
    of a violation the subject experiences in the project of being
    recognized as such.
    Epistemic skepticism: By drawing on recognized demands of
    subject, critique might be systematically unable to account for the
    conditions of existence of these subjects.

    View Slide

  11. Pessimism (5)
    Summary:
    ontological skepticism (recognition-based critique might, in
    virtue of its ontology, be unable to criticize norms of
    recognition)
    normative skepticism
    epistemic skepticism

    View Slide

  12. Pessimism (6)
    If a model of normative critique presupposes the validity of claims
    instituted in practices of recognition, the following question arises:
    Is such a model still sufficiently capable of subjecting these practices
    themselves to a radical critique? Or is the whole perspective of
    normative critique so dependent on the existing practices of
    recognition that these practices effectively succeed in immunizing
    themselves against criticism?

    View Slide

  13. The failure of pessimism as a model of critique

    View Slide

  14. The argument
    An idealized argument (see handout):
    (P1) That some individual is a subject is not a description of some
    self-standing properties or capacities of that individual, but rather of
    the social status of that individual within a specific discursive
    practice wherein it is treated as such.
    (P2) This practice is itself governed by a set of rules R˜1 specifying
    who may legitimately be treated as a subject.

    View Slide

  15. The argument
    (P3) Among these constitutive rules R˜1 which define who counts
    as a subject, there may be rules that specify that, in order to count
    as a subject, an individual must accept responsibility for her actions
    according to a set of rules R˜2.
    Example: in order to count as a discursive subject, you must accept
    (but not necessarily always follow) the rules of logical consistency as
    valid for you.
    (C1) Thus, in order to be treated as a subject, an individual must
    accept the legitimacy of these rules R˜2.

    View Slide

  16. The argument
    (P3) A normative critique of social practices is a judgement about
    this practice which expresses a justified demand of persons who are
    affected in some way by this practice.
    (P4) “To be justified” is a social status which only discursive
    subjects can have.
    (C2) Thus, engaging in a normative critique presupposes that there
    are discursive subjects and that their demands and their perspective
    are a valid reference point for this critique.

    View Slide

  17. The argument
    (C3 – Pessimist thesis) This perspective thus either ontologically
    or normatively presupposes the normative validity of either R1 or R2
    or is epistemically unable to recover the conditions under which R1
    or R2 have acquired their normative force.
    (C4) Thus, the uncritical assumption that recognition is a valid
    foundation for social critique legitimizes the domination which these
    rules exert upon individuals or the violation which the imposition of
    these rules constitutes for these individuals.

    View Slide

  18. The problem of the pessimist model
    All forms of critique of recognition seem to be either based upon
    some claim of a subject which it is justified to make in virtue of
    having a legitimate claim to some form of recognition. But the fact
    that some subject has a legitimate claim either is true in virtue of
    the social status of that subject - then we are back within the
    optimist model of critique. Or this claim is true independently of
    social practices: Then we must be committed to some form of moral
    realism which makes a critique of recognition unnecessary.

    View Slide

  19. Hegelian replies

    View Slide

  20. A Hegelian argument
    (1) The perspective of normative critique is bound to some
    institutionally conditioned self-understanding, constituted by our
    relations of recognition.
    (2) Each such self-understanding includes standards of justification
    which can be used to critically evaluate that self-understanding.
    (3) From within a discursive order, we can employ the resources of
    this order to determine which of its rules we can reflectively
    endorse according to its own standards.
    Consequence: We can draw a difference between normatively
    justifiable and normatively unjustifiable rules of recognition
    according to a standard of reflective acceptibility.

    View Slide

  21. Problem with the Hegelian argument
    This standard is too weak: It evaluates practices as justified which
    are reflexively acceptable to their members (“only”) in virtue of the
    fact that they produce forms of subjectivity that are necessarily
    unable to criticize the constitutive rules of their subjectivation.

    View Slide

  22. A new start

    View Slide

  23. Resources within the Hegelian tradition
    There is a distinction between:
    first-order attitudes towards matters of fact
    second-order attitudes towards attitudes of others
    second-order attitudes towards the rules which define the space
    of possible attitudes

    View Slide

  24. The Hegelian solution, again
    Reconstruction of the Hegelian argument:
    The rules R of recognition / subjectivation of a practice P are
    warranted iff those individuals who count as subjects within P due
    to their acceptance of its rules R are, according to R, justified in
    having an affirmative second-order attitude towards R.

    View Slide

  25. A new attempt
    A practice is only ideological if its constitutive rules mandate
    constraints on potentially critical second-order attitudes towards the
    very same rules / if its constitutive rules limit the scope of aspects
    in relation to which the justification of its constitutive rules can be
    challenged.

    View Slide

  26. Ideological recognition
    A practice of subjectivation is ideological (if and) only if individuals
    can only become recognized as discursive subjects within that
    practice by accepting limitations upon the scope of their
    second-order attitudes.
    Example: Gender as ideology (recognition as a discursive subject
    depends on acceptance of an understanding of gender norms as
    natural)

    View Slide

  27. Ideological recognition
    Two new insights:
    not all constraints on subject-formation are ideological
    ideological character always a matter of degree

    View Slide

  28. The resulting model of critique
    The ideological character of a practice of subjectivation is only
    an apt object for critique if we assume that constraining
    second-order attitudes of persons violates a claim they have.
    Most plausible candidate: autonomy.
    Critique of ideological subjectivation thus presupposes a
    standpoint of a practice of mutual recognition of persons as
    entitled to autonomy.

    View Slide

  29. Pessimism
    Contrast to pessimist accounts: Rejection of a premise necessary for
    (C3) - norms of subjectivation do not already per se immunize a
    practice of recognition (and a critique that argues from within it)
    against radical critique.

    View Slide

  30. Conclusion
    A suitably revised and extended Hegelian conception can survive the
    challenge of recognition as ideology.

    View Slide