Upgrade to Pro — share decks privately, control downloads, hide ads and more …

Philosophical Ethics

GeorgeMatthews
December 30, 2016

Philosophical Ethics

Third slideshow for an online course.

GeorgeMatthews

December 30, 2016
Tweet

More Decks by GeorgeMatthews

Other Decks in Education

Transcript

  1. ! This slide show presents a series of philosophical theories

    on the nature of and justification for value judgments about what is right and what is wrong.
  2. ! This slide show presents a series of philosophical theories

    on the nature of and justification for value judgments about what is right and what is wrong. ! Each of these theories has had many supporters throughout history and each continues to have supporters now.
  3. ! This slide show presents a series of philosophical theories

    on the nature of and justification for value judgments about what is right and what is wrong. ! Each of these theories has had many supporters throughout history and each continues to have supporters now. ! In evaluating each of these theories consider how well supported it is by the argument given as well as any positive and negative implications it may have.
  4. Cultural Relativism Ruth Benedict 1887 – 1948 “The trouble with

    life isn’t that there is no answer, it’s that there are so many answers.”
  5. Cultural Relativism Ruth Benedict 1887 – 1948 “The trouble with

    life isn’t that there is no answer, it’s that there are so many answers.” Ruth Benedict was an American anthropologist whose studies of other cultures convinced her that there was no one set of universally valid values.
  6. Cultural Relativism Ruth Benedict 1887 – 1948 We all disagree

    about the meaning of terms such as “right” and ”wrong.” Thus nothing is truly right or wrong, only right or wrong from a particular perspective. the cultural differences argument
  7. Cultural Relativism We all disagree about the meaning of terms

    such as “right” and ”wrong.” Thus nothing is truly right or wrong, only right or wrong from a particular perspective. the cultural differences argument Relativism claims that the whole idea of universally valid values is mistaken, since value judgments depend on one’s perspective. Although this may seem to be an appealing approach to value judgments, it has its problems.
  8. Cultural Relativism We all disagree about the meaning of terms

    such as “right” and ”wrong.” Thus nothing is truly right or wrong, only right or wrong from a particular perspective. the cultural differences argument The major argument for cultural relativism asserts that the fact of cultural diversity negates the possibility of their being universal values. But is this really valid reasoning?
  9. Cultural Relativism We all disagree about the meaning of terms

    such as “right” and ”wrong.” Thus nothing is truly right or wrong, only right or wrong from a particular perspective. the cultural differences argument The premise of this argument is certainly true. But then what follows from this fact?
  10. Cultural Relativism We all disagree about the meaning of terms

    such as “right” and ”wrong.” Thus nothing is truly right or wrong, only right or wrong from a particular perspective. the cultural differences argument Note that the conclusion makes a much stronger claim than the premise does. It says that because we disagree on something nobody could possibly be correct. But this just doesn’t follow, hence this argument is INVALID.
  11. Cultural Relativism We all disagree about the meaning of terms

    such as “right” and ”wrong.” Thus nothing is truly right or wrong, only right or wrong from a particular perspective. the cultural differences argument Not only is the main argument for relativism invalid, this position also implies that nothing is just plain wrong – not even genocide – as long as somebody believes that it is acceptable.
  12. Cultural Relativism We all disagree about the meaning of terms

    such as “right” and ”wrong.” Thus nothing is truly right or wrong, only right or wrong from a particular perspective. the cultural differences argument But what if different cultures agree deep down on basic values even if they may implement those values in widely divergent ways?
  13. Divine Command Theory Saint Augustine 354 – 430 “A thing

    is good and pleasant only because it is connected to Him. Use it apart from its Source, and it will come to taste bitter. ”
  14. Divine Command Theory Saint Augustine 354 – 430 “A thing

    is good and pleasant only because it is connected to Him. Use it apart from its Source, and it will come to taste bitter. ” Augustine converted to Christianity as an adult and then went on to become one of the most influential Christian writers of all times; his ideas made an indelible mark on the young religion. He defended the idea that God’s will determines what is right and wrong.
  15. Divine Command Theory Saint Augustine 354 – 430 The only

    way for moral commands to be objective and binding is for them to have been issued by an absolute moral authority. There are some objective and binding moral commands, some things we just shouldn’t do. So there must be an absolute moral au- thority and this is God. the argument from moral authority
  16. Divine Command Theory The only way for moral commands to

    be objective and binding is for them to have been issued by an absolute moral authority. There are some objective and binding moral commands, some things we just shouldn’t do. So there must be an absolute moral au- thority and this is God. the argument from moral authority Divine command theory argues that we can only make sense of moral ideas if they are based on the commands of an ultimate moral authority.
  17. Divine Command Theory The only way for moral commands to

    be objective and binding is for them to have been issued by an absolute moral authority. There are some objective and binding moral commands, some things we just shouldn’t do. So there must be an absolute moral au- thority and this is God. the argument from moral authority This seems like a strong claim, but some things seem like they are just wrong no matter what – such as killing babies for fun.
  18. Divine Command Theory The only way for moral commands to

    be objective and binding is for them to have been issued by an absolute moral authority. There are some objective and binding moral commands, some things we just shouldn’t do. So there must be an absolute moral au- thority and this is God. the argument from moral authority Although this argument is valid, there is a difficult problem with trying to base moral rules on divine commands.
  19. Divine Command Theory The only way for moral commands to

    be objective and binding is for them to have been issued by an absolute moral authority. There are some objective and binding moral commands, some things we just shouldn’t do. So there must be an absolute moral au- thority and this is God. the argument from moral authority If God says that murder is wrong, does this mean that if He had said murder was OK, would this make it so? If not, then how can God be the source of moral rules?
  20. Natural Law Theory Thomas Aquinas 1225 – 1274 “The natural

    law is nothing else than the rational creature’s participation in the eternal law. ”
  21. Natural Law Theory Thomas Aquinas 1225 – 1274 “The natural

    law is nothing else than the rational creature’s participation in the eternal law. ” Aquinas held that being ethical involved living up to one’s potential as a self- governing, rational being, whose passions are held in check. He followed Aristotle in thinking that all natural things have an “end” or natural goal built-in to them although unlike Aristotle he thought that this end was built-in to us by God.
  22. Natural Law Theory Thomas Aquinas 1225 – 1274 Human beings

    have a set of built-in functions and capacities. Realizing these natural functions and capacities is better than not doing so. So human nature provides a guide for ethical action. the argument from moral authority
  23. Natural Law Theory Human beings have a set of built-in

    functions and capacities. Realizing these natural functions and capacities is better than not doing so. So human nature provides a guide for ethical action. the argument from moral authority Natural law theory claims that some things are inherently wrong: those things that violate the natural functions and capacities built in to us.
  24. Natural Law Theory Human beings have a set of built-in

    functions and capacities. Realizing these natural functions and capacities is better than not doing so. So human nature provides a guide for ethical action. the argument from moral authority Is what is natural always what is best?
  25. Natural Law Theory Human beings have a set of built-in

    functions and capacities. Realizing these natural functions and capacities is better than not doing so. So human nature provides a guide for ethical action. the argument from moral authority Isn’t it up to us to decide what is right and what is wrong, whatever human nature may tell us?
  26. Psychological Egoism Max Stirner 1806 – 1856 “For me you

    are nothing but – my food, even as I too am fed upon and turned to use by you.”
  27. Psychological Egoism Max Stirner 1806 – 1856 “For me you

    are nothing but – my food, even as I too am fed upon and turned to use by you.” Max Stirner was a German philosopher who held that all actions are by definition self-centered since we all must act on the basis of our own plans and ideas. Perhaps he was a product of his own times, the early days of industrial capitalism in Europe when workers were ruthlessly exploited in appalling condi- tions as documented by Charles Dickens and Karl Marx.
  28. Psychological Egoism Max Stirner 1806 – 1856 All decisions are

    made by individuals based on their own understanding and interests. Thus all decisions made by anyone must be self-serving and any apparently altruistic action must have an underlying selfish motive. in defense of psychological egoism
  29. Psychological Egoism All decisions are made by individuals based on

    their own understanding and interests. Thus all decisions made by anyone must be self-serving and any apparently altruistic action must have an underlying selfish motive. in defense of psychological egoism Psychological egoism claims that we cannot, by definition, act for the sake of others.
  30. Psychological Egoism All decisions are made by individuals based on

    their own understanding and interests. Thus all decisions made by anyone must be self-serving and any apparently altruistic action must have an underlying selfish motive. in defense of psychological egoism If this is the case then morality would be a pointless thing to try to follow.
  31. Psychological Egoism All decisions are made by individuals based on

    their own understanding and interests. Thus all decisions made by anyone must be self-serving and any apparently altruistic action must have an underlying selfish motive. in defense of psychological egoism But doesn’t this theory paint an excessively cynical view of human beings? We can certainly interpret all action in terms of hidden motives, but does this mean that is all that moves us?
  32. Ethical Egoism Ayn Rand 1905 – 1982 “Self-sacrifice? But it

    is precisely the self that cannot and must not be sacrificed.”
  33. Ethical Egoism Ayn Rand 1905 – 1982 “Self-sacrifice? But it

    is precisely the self that cannot and must not be sacrificed.” Ayn Rand was a highly influential novelist who emigrated from Russia to the U.S. She defended the capitalist idea that the good of all was only to be achieved by ignoring the demands of others and pursuing selfish gain. Among her contemporary followers are Alan Greenspan and Ron Paul who named his son Rand after her.
  34. Ethical Egoism Ayn Rand 1905 – 1982 The most important

    human value is the value of the individual. Acting for the sake of others requires denying the value of the individual. Thus one should never act for the sake of others. Rand’s argument against altruism
  35. Ethical Egoism The most important human value is the value

    of the individual. Acting for the sake of others requires denying the value of the individual. Thus one should never act for the sake of others. Rand’s argument against altruism Aren’t there also values to be found in cooperative activity?
  36. Ethical Egoism The most important human value is the value

    of the individual. Acting for the sake of others requires denying the value of the individual. Thus one should never act for the sake of others. Rand’s argument against altruism Is life really a “zero sum game,” in which my benefit requires your loss?
  37. Ethical Egoism The most important human value is the value

    of the individual. Acting for the sake of others requires denying the value of the individual. Thus one should never act for the sake of others. Rand’s argument against altruism Is it always rational to ignore others’ interests?
  38. Social Contract Theory Thomas Hobbes 1588 – 1674 Without enforceable

    social rules we should expect “continual fear, and danger of violent death; And the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.”
  39. Social Contract Theory Thomas Hobbes 1588 – 1674 Without enforceable

    social rules we should expect “continual fear, and danger of violent death; And the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” Thomas Hobbes was the first modern political philosopher. He thought that social rules – moral and political – should be based on self- interest. We all have an interest in living under the rule of law rather than in the anarchy of the “state of nature.”.
  40. Social Contract Theory Thomas Hobbes 1588 – 1674 We owe

    allegiance to rules only if they serve our interests. Social rules are in our best interests to follow since living by them is better than fending for ourselves. So we should follow the basic rules of society and trade some individual liberty for the rule of law. In Defense of the Social Contract
  41. Social Contract Theory We owe allegiance to rules only if

    they serve our interests. Social rules are in our best interests to follow since living by them is better than fending for ourselves. So we should follow the basic rules of society and trade some individual liberty for the rule of law. In Defense of the Social Contract We all share basic interests such as life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness.
  42. Social Contract Theory We owe allegiance to rules only if

    they serve our interests. Social rules are in our best interests to follow since living by them is better than fending for ourselves. So we should follow the basic rules of society and trade some individual liberty for the rule of law. In Defense of the Social Contract In a state of nature we have greater liberty, but also much greater insecurity than in society‘.
  43. Social Contract Theory We owe allegiance to rules only if

    they serve our interests. Social rules are in our best interests to follow since living by them is better than fending for ourselves. So we should follow the basic rules of society and trade some individual liberty for the rule of law. In Defense of the Social Contract Even if we may have an interest in accepting basic rules, what if the payoff for cheating on these rules is high enough to tempt us to cheat?
  44. Social Contract Theory We owe allegiance to rules only if

    they serve our interests. Social rules are in our best interests to follow since living by them is better than fending for ourselves. So we should follow the basic rules of society and trade some individual liberty for the rule of law. In Defense of the Social Contract What if we could get away with not paying taxes, or otherwise taking advantage of “public goods” for private gain – why shouldn’t we?
  45. The Tragedy of the Commons Even if we all have

    an interest in a clean world . . .
  46. The Tragedy of the Commons we also all have an

    interest in getting something for nothing . . .
  47. Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 1806 – 1873 “The Greatest-Happiness Principle

    holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.”
  48. Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 1806 – 1873 “The Greatest-Happiness Principle

    holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.” John Stuart Mill was a British economist, philosopher and social reformer. He assumed that humans were self- interested, yet that we could also be convinced to act for the good of others. Mills philosophy of utilitarianism remains popular to this day among economists and policy makers.
  49. Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 1806 – 1873 We are all

    after the same thing – happiness. There is no reason why my happiness should be considered more important than anyone else’s happiness So we should always act to maximize overall happiness, by choosing what leads to the greatest benefit for the most people involved. An argument for utilitarianism
  50. Utilitarianism We are all after the same thing – happiness.

    There is no reason why my happiness should be considered more important than anyone else’s happiness So we should always act to maximize overall happiness, by choosing what leads to the greatest benefit for the most people involved. An argument for utilitarianism Even if different things might make different people happy we all share the quest for happiness.
  51. Utilitarianism We are all after the same thing – happiness.

    There is no reason why my happiness should be considered more important than anyone else’s happiness So we should always act to maximize overall happiness, by choosing what leads to the greatest benefit for the most people involved. An argument for utilitarianism If happiness is valuable in itself then what reason can I have for saying that my happiness counts but yours doesn’t?
  52. Utilitarianism We are all after the same thing – happiness.

    There is no reason why my happiness should be considered more important than anyone else’s happiness So we should always act to maximize overall happiness, by choosing what leads to the greatest benefit for the most people involved. An argument for utilitarianism Utilitarianism bases the value of an action purely on the consequences of that action.
  53. Is what is “good” always what is “right?” How do

    we know what the ultimate consequences of our actions are?
  54. Kantian ethics Immanuel Kant 1724 – 1804 “Act in such

    a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of another, always at the same time as an end and never simply as a means.”
  55. Kantian ethics Immanuel Kant 1724 – 1804 “Act in such

    a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of another, always at the same time as an end and never simply as a means.” Kant was a major figure in the intellectual movement known as the Enlightenment. He sought to provide a rational basis for the values of the French Revolution – liberty, equality, fraternity.
  56. Kantian ethics Immanuel Kant 1724 – 1804 Acting selfishly always

    involves assuming that others will follow the rules I break. An act can be a moral act only if it can be universally accepted. Selfish action cannot be universally accepted since it contradicts itself. So selfish action is fundamentally wrong. Kant’s argument for universal morality
  57. Kantian ethics Acting selfishly always involves assuming that others will

    follow the rules I break. An act can be a moral act only if it can be universally accepted. Selfish action cannot be universally accepted since it contradicts itself. So selfish action is fundamentally wrong. Kant’s argument for universal morality If I lie or make false promises I am assuming that you value telling the truth and keeping one’s promises otherwise you’d never take me at my word.
  58. Kantian ethics Acting selfishly always involves assuming that others will

    follow the rules I break. An act can be a moral act only if it can be universally accepted. Selfish action cannot be universally accepted since it contradicts itself. So selfish action is fundamentally wrong. Kant’s argument for universal morality To say that something is morally acceptable or unacceptable is to make an unconditional claim.
  59. Kantian ethics Acting selfishly always involves assuming that others will

    follow the rules I break. An act can be a moral act only if it can be universally accepted. Selfish action cannot be universally accepted since it contradicts itself. So selfish action is fundamentally wrong. Kant’s argument for universal morality What makes immoral action wrong is that it fails to treat others as equals by acting on a double standard.
  60. Kantian ethics Acting selfishly always involves assuming that others will

    follow the rules I break. An act can be a moral act only if it can be universally accepted. Selfish action cannot be universally accepted since it contradicts itself. So selfish action is fundamentally wrong. Kant’s argument for universal morality This is the basis for the idea that there are universal human rights – fundamental limits in the way we should treat each other.
  61. Universal Rights Democracy is based on the idea that we

    all deserve equal protection of the law.
  62. Feminist Ethics Carol Gilligan 1936 – “My research suggests that

    men and women may speak different languages that they assume are the same, using similar words to encode disparate experiences of self and social relationships.”
  63. Feminist Ethics Carol Gilligan 1936 – “My research suggests that

    men and women may speak different languages that they assume are the same, using similar words to encode disparate experiences of self and social relationships.” Carol Gilligan refused to accept that standard models of moral development did justice to the moral experience of women.
  64. Feminist Ethics Carol Gilligan 1936 – Philosophy and psychology presume

    that morality requires following impartial and universal rules. This “masculine” approach to moral decision-making leaves out “feminine” concerns with concrete relationships. A complete picture of morality requires balancing abstract rules with particular relationships. Gilligan’s argument
  65. Feminist Ethics Philosophy and psychology presume that morality requires following

    impartial and universal rules. This “masculine” approach to moral decision-making leaves out “feminine” concerns with concrete relationships. A complete picture of morality requires balancing abstract rules with particular relationships. Gilligan’s argument The dominant theory of moral development, that of Lawrence Kohlberg, argues that moral ma- turity requires following universal rules regardless of the human costs involved.
  66. Feminist Ethics Philosophy and psychology presume that morality requires following

    impartial and universal rules. This “masculine” approach to moral decision-making leaves out “feminine” concerns with concrete relationships. A complete picture of morality requires balancing abstract rules with particular relationships. Gilligan’s argument In Kohlberg’s tests female subjects tended to focus on social contexts at the expense of universal rules.
  67. Feminist Ethics Philosophy and psychology presume that morality requires following

    impartial and universal rules. This “masculine” approach to moral decision-making leaves out “feminine” concerns with concrete relationships. A complete picture of morality requires balancing abstract rules with particular relationships. Gilligan’s argument Rather than accept that these subjects were “under-developed” Gilligan defends the idea of differing and complementary moral “voices.”
  68. Feminist Ethics Philosophy and psychology presume that morality requires following

    impartial and universal rules. This “masculine” approach to moral decision-making leaves out “feminine” concerns with concrete relationships. A complete picture of morality requires balancing abstract rules with particular relationships. Gilligan’s argument Do men and women have different moral “styles?”